IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
25
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
IRISH CONSTITUTIONAL PROPERTY RIGHTS
AND NORMATIVE THEORIES OF PROPERTY
Abstract: Irish courts have failed to engage with the wording of the constitutional property rights clauses, a
failure justified on the basis that the wording of these clauses is ambiguous. Through the application of
normative theories of property, this article seeks to show that the clauses contain an unambiguously
communitarian meaning. It is argued that courts have at times defaulted to a liberal understanding of property
as exemplified by cases like Blake-Madigan. However, this 'liberalism creep' has largely now abated and
recent judgments in areas such as planning law show the emerging predominance of communitarianism in
constitutional property rights adjudication.
Author: James McGovern B.A. (Dubl.), LL.M (Northumbria), Solicitor.
Introduction
Irish courts have failed to engage with the wording of the constitutional property rights
clauses, a failure that has been justified on the basis that these clauses are ambiguous in
nature.
1
Courts and commentators have often talked past one another, some suggesting that
the property clauses contain communitarian values and others suggesting they contain liberal
values, at times without employing a thorough analysis of the area.
2
Evidence of the failure
to engage with the property clauses and ultimately to clarify them may be seen in the ongoing
uncertainty over whether certain political proposals to address the Housing Crisis would fall
foul of the constitutional property rights provisions.
3
The failure to adequately interpret the
constitutional provisions has created an ambiguity that has arguably given rise to proposals
for a referendum to insert new wording into the Constitution to clarify the Oireachtas
powers in the area of housing.
4
This article asks how Irish constitutional law understands the values through which property
rights must be interpreted. It will apply two normative theories of property, communitarian
and liberal, as an aid to determining this question.
Utilising the insights of the property theory set out in the first section of the article, the
second section will conclude that the constitutional property wording is imbued with
communitarian values. The origin of the Constitution and the significance of the Land
Question will be critical to the analysis. It is argued that Irish courts, in a similar way to courts
in other common law jurisdictions, have at times defaulted to a liberal understanding of
property as occurred in cases such as Blake-Madigan. However, this liberalism creep has
largely now abated and recent judgments in areas such as planning law are given as examples
of the emerging predominance of communitarian considerations in constitutional property
rights adjudication.
* I am grateful to Dr Gabriel Brennan and Dr Brian Barry for reading earlier drafts and providing me with helpful comments.
1
Gerard Hogan, ‘The Constitution, Property Rights and Proportionality’ (1997) 32 Irish Jurist 373, 375.
2
For example, Mr Justice O’Donnell, writing extrajudicially, has suggested the Constitution contains liberal values with
respect to property rights. See O'Donnell, ‘Property Rights in the Irish Constitution: Rights for Rich People, or a Pillar of
a Free Society’, in Oran Doyle and Eoin Carolan (eds), The Irish Constitution: Governance and Values (Thomson Round 2008)
413. In contrast, Mr Justice Brian Walsh, writing extrajudicially, has argued for the idea that the Constitution contains
communitarian values on property rights. See Walsh, ‘The Judicial Power, Justice and the Constitution of Ireland’ in Deirdre
Curtin and David O’Keeffe (eds), Constitutional Adjudication in European Community and National Law: Essays for the Honourable
Mr Justice TF O’Higgins (Butterworth 1992) 147.
3
See Rachael Walsh, ‘No legal reason Government can’t limit sale of new homes’ The Irish Times (Dublin, 7 May 2021).
4
'Why a Referendum' (Home for Good) <https://www.homeforgood.ie/referendum> accessed 28 May 2023.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
26
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
Normative Theories of Property
Overview
This section will outline the two most relevant normative theories of property for Irish
constitutional property rights: communitarian theory and liberal theory. These theories will
then be used as an interpretative aid in the following section when analysing the Irish
constitutional position.
It is useful to introduce this discussion with a brief overview of constitutional interpretation.
Daly argues that the interpretivist approach has dominated in Irish constitutional law, that
is where constitutional provisions are interpreted so as to express an underlying philosophy.
5
Mr Justice Brian Walsh writing extrajudicially, argues each of our judges must work from a
philosophical conviction which does not differ from the philosophy underlying and
informing the Constitution.
6
Citing Sunstein,
7
Whyte argues that all judges necessarily come
to constitutional adjudication with a set of 'preinterpretative values'.
8
This follows from the
fact that a given passage in a constitution will often not have one clear and definitive meaning
and a judge must select which meaning is the most plausible.
The text of the Irish Constitution refers to property rights twice; the first reference being in
Article 40.3.2° where, under the heading of 'Personal Rights', it is stated that the State shall
protect, as best it may, the property rights of every citizen from unjust attack. The second
reference is Article 43 which asserts that there is a natural right to the private ownership of
external goods and that the State accordingly guarantees to pass no law attempting to abolish
the right of private ownership or the general right to transfer, bequeath and inherit property.
Article 43 goes on to state that the exercise of property rights ought to be regulated by the
principles of social justice which means that the State may delimit property rights with a view
to reconciling their exercise with the exigencies of the common good.
In discussing the values which permeate the Constitution, legal commentators have posited
a dichotomy between communitarian and liberal content. Van der Walt has discussed this
dichotomy specifically with reference to Article 43 of the Constitution, comparing it to the
constitutions of South Africa and Germany in terms of its communitarian impetus.
9
This liberal-communitarian dichotomy is crucial to understanding how constitutional
property rights have been interpreted. This is because, as Pistor has pointed out,
constitutions presume property rights but do not define them nor do they specify who has
the right to define them.
10
Thus it is left to judges to determine how property rights are
interpreted and what values, be they liberal, communitarian or otherwise, are brought to bear
in that interpretative process. Relatedly, Allen discusses the possibility that the idea of value-
free judicial interpretation in the context of constitutional property rights has in practice been
a way for liberal values-influenced judiciaries to incorporate liberal presuppositions into their
adjudication.
11
5
Eoin Daly, ‘Public Philosophy and Constitutional Interpretation after Natural Law: Republican Horizons’ in Eoin Carolan
(ed), The Constitution of Ireland: Perspectives and Prospects (Bloomsbury Professional 2012) 91.
6
Brian Walsh (n 2) 147.
7
CR Sunstein, The Partial Constitution (Harvard UP 1993) 93.
8
Gerard Whyte, Social Inclusion and the Legal System: Public Interest Law in Ireland (Institute of Public Administration 2002) 26.
9
AJ Van Der Walt, ‘The Protection of Private Property under the Irish Constitution: A Comparative and Theoretical
Perspective’ in Oran Doyle and Eoin Carolan (eds) The Irish Constitution: Governance and Values (Thomson Round Hall 2008)
398.
10
Katerina Pistor, The Code of Capital: How the Law Creates Wealth and Inequality (Princeton UP 2019) 68.
11
Tom Allen, The Right to Property in Commonwealth Constitutions (Cambridge UP 2000) 106.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
27
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
Irish judges have historically understood the political implications surrounding the
interpretation of the property clauses of the Constitution and have, at times, done their
utmost to avoid interpreting the meaning and values contained therein. In Pigs Marketing
Board v Donnelly, when discussing social justice as the term appears in Article 43, Hanna J
stated that it was a:
nebulous phrase, involving no question of law for the Courts, but questions
of ethics, morals, economics, and sociology, which are, in my opinion,
beyond the determination of a Court of law, but which may be, in their
various aspects, within the consideration of the Oireachtas, as representing
the people, when framing the law.
12
That case is now considered bad law in that the High Court in its judgment failed to carry
out its duty to interpret the Constitution.
13
However, commentators who have been satisfied
to write off Pigs Marketing as bad law have themselves sought to avoid interpreting Article 43
and its terminology. Hogan has called the language of Articles 40.3.2° and 43 so inherently
subjective and open-textured that its interpretation is replete with difficulties.
14
In the same
article, he sympathised with the courtsapproach in avoiding interpreting the language in
favour of a workable judicial methodology centring on the use of the proportionality test.
15
O’Neill has similarly written that the phrases of Article 43 are so broad and subjective as to
be of little real guidance.
16
Thus there has been a reluctance among both the courts and legal
commentators to fully engage with the language of the Constitution’s property provisions
and the values contained therein. Many have preferred to side-step the issue altogether and
to replace the language of the Constitution with alternatives such as the proportionality test.
The following sections of the article will set out the aspects of the communitarian and liberal
theories of property relevant in an Irish context before returning to the actual wording of
the Constitution, its influences and how it has been interpreted in order to understand where
the Irish Constitution falls along the communitarian versus liberal values axis.
The Communitarian Position
The communitarian theory of property emphasises the obligations of property rights holders
toward their communities and the potential uses of property law to bring about human
flourishing.
17
Communitarians envisage that the social obligations of property rights holders
may, through democratic decision-making, be fulfilled through property law.
18
While the
term ‘communitarian’ is a recognised one in the context of Irish property rights discussion,
progressive property theoryis the approximate United States equivalent.
19
Walsh’s recent
monograph has attempted to apply some of the insights of progressive property theorists to
an Irish context.
20
Progressive property theorists promote a theory of property rights and
12
[1939] IR 413, 418.
13
See, inter alia, Rachael Walsh, ‘The Constitution, Property Rights and Proportionality: A Reappraisal’ (2009) 31 Dublin
University Law Journal 1, 13; Donal Barrington, ‘Private Property under the Irish Constitution’ (1973) 8 Irish Jurist 1, 6.
14
Hogan (n 1)375.
15
ibid 377.
16
Ailbhe O’Neill, ‘Property Rights and the Power of Eminent Domain’ in Oran Doyle and Eoin Carolan (eds) The Irish
Constitution: Governance and Values (Thomson Round Hall 2008) 439.
17
JW Singer, ‘Democratic Estates: Property Law in a Free and Democratic Society’ (2009) 94 Cornell L Rev 1009, 1010.
18
Eduardo Peñalver, ‘Land Virtues’ 94 Cornell L Rev 821, 869-71.
19
For the use of the term ‘communitarian’ in Ireland, see, for example, Rachael Walsh, ‘Private Property Rights in the
Drafting of the Irish Constitution: A Communitarian Compromise’ (2011) 33 Dublin University Law Journal 86.
20
Walsh, Property Rights and Social Justice: Progressive Property in Action (Cambridge UP 2021) 45-6.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
28
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
values which are particularly useful in interpreting the Irish Constitution because they draw
from many of the same intellectual sources from which the Constitution itself has drawn.
Progressive property theorists accept the insights of Aquinas and Thomism,
21
the influence
of which on the Irish Constitution has been long recognised and will be discussed further
below. Peñalver, for example, argues for the reconfiguration of property law rules in order
to promote human flourishing, a theory grounded in the thought of Aristotle and Aquinas.
22
In common with Lyall’s interpretation of property rights as ultimately consisting of relations
between people,
23
Aquinas similarly viewed property rights, in contrast to liberal theorists, as
concerning matters of justice between people, not just human relationships to things.
24
His
justification for property being allocated to private individuals rather than the community as
a whole was that holding property in common would lead to a neglect and misuse of
resources akin to a tragedy of the commons. However, this allocation was subject to the
proviso that the use of resources was ultimately common; that all possessions are in some
sense morally available to those in need. Aquinas sets out three categories of resources or
property: (a) a category corresponding to absolute necessity, resources required for one’s
own survival and one’s dependants’ survival, (b) a category corresponding to relative
necessity, including maintaining one’s responsibilities to one’s household, for example by
educating one’s children and maintaining one’s business, and (c) a category called the
superflua, resources remaining following provision of resources for absolute and relative
necessity.
25
Justice, not charity, requires an individual to distribute one’s superflua to those
lacking in their provisions as to absolute and relative necessity. Aquinas believed that rulers
had a responsibility to provide a fair distribution of resources to their subjects.
26
Finnis
concludes that Thomist property theory entails that states should legislate to ensure superflua
are distributed accordingly.
27
The 'general justice' which Aquinas believed governed property
relations, broadly corresponds with the notion of social justice promulgated by the Catholic
Church in papal encyclicals such as Quadragesimo Anno.
28
The ideas of Thomism have been
extremely influential in Catholic social teaching and it is via this route that they become
particularly relevant in an Irish constitutional context.
Underkuffler emphasises that property is an allocative choice by government and society.
29
Property is unlike the other liberal civil rights often coupled with it, e.g. voting rights or free
speech rights, in that allocating property to one person necessarily excludes it from another.
30
It is these characteristics that leads Kingston to argue against the traditional liberal
categorisation and alternatively to group property as an economic rather than a civil right.
31
Underkuffler similarly discusses how property cannot effectively exist without the State to
protect it through its police power and legal institutions.
32
In an Irish context, Pettit makes
21
See Rachael Walsh, ‘Property, Human Flourishing and St Thomas Aquinas’ (2018) 31 Canadian Journal of Law and
Jurisprudence 197.
22
Peñalver (n 18) 869.
23
Niamh Howlin and Noel McGrath, Lyall on Land Law (4th edn, Thomson Reuters 2018) 2.
24
John Finnis, Aquinas: Moral, Political and Legal Theory (Oxford UP 1998) 188-9.
25
ibid 191.
26
Walsh (n 21) 214.
27
Finnis, Aquinas (n 24) 195.
28
John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford UP 2011) 461-2.
29
LS Underkuffler, ‘What Does the Constitutional Protection of Property Mean’ (2016) 5 Brigham-Kanner Property Rights
Conference Journal 109, 120-1.
30
LS Underkuffler, ‘A Special Right’ (1996) 71 Notre Dame L Rev 1033, 1038.
31
James Kingston, ‘Rich People Have Rights Too? The Status of Property as a Fundamental Human Right’ in Liz Heffernan
(ed), Human Rights: A European Perspective (Round Hall 1994) 286.
32
Underkuffler (n 30) 1046.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
29
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
the same communitarian point.
33
Where liberals see property as a right that protects people
as they interact with society, progressive theorists argue that the existence of the institution
of private property itself presumes society. There must first be society to create and enforce
property rights.
34
Singer argues that liberal thinkers have failed to take account of the historical development
of property.
35
He references the fact that land in the United States, following dispossession
of the Native Americans, was allocated to European settlers by government grant. The
justification in that instance was that European settlers would use the land more
productively.
36
In an English context, a similar justification based on efficiency and
productivity was employed by the State when it enclosed the commons and divided it
amongst large landowners.
37
Thus, the distribution of property today has its origins in
historical allocations justified by reference to the common good. In an Irish context, the
Land Acts are highly salient to this point and will be discussed below.
Communitarian thinkers can rely on the fact that land law in England and Ireland originated
in Anglo-Norman feudal law and therefore always contained a notion of the obligations of
property owners.
38
The conception of property rights as absolute derives from Roman law,
as does the distinction between dominium (property) and imperium (sovereignty).
39
Despite
favouring a liberal conception, Smith has discussed how the feudal origins of the common
law gives property in common law jurisdictions today a distinctive character as compared
with its Roman-law based civil neighbours.
40
A hard distinction between property and
sovereignty has long been recognised as having a dubious philosophical and logical basis.
Cohen describes how property entails a 'sovereign power compelling service and obedience',
a relationship clearer during the feudal system but obtaining still in the modern economy,
for example, in the necessity to pay rent to a landlord and be governed by her rules.
41
Property
is, although admittedly limited by law, a form of delegated sovereignty.
Communitarians recognise the inherent political nature and implications of property rights.
Walsh alludes to the importance of political considerations in judicial determination of
constitutional property rights cases and quotes Nedelsky that property implicates the core
issues of politics, distributive justice, and the allocation of power.
42
This author respectfully
considers this to be an understatement. As is argued in Lyall, property rights fundamentally
structure social relations.
43
Politics is the elephant in the room of any discussion of property.
The Liberal Position
Underkuffler characterises the American constitutional idea of property as a 'bulwark
surrounding the sphere of individual liberty' and as 'an absolute and inalienable right, which
provides a bedrock or protection'.
44
This is effectively the liberal view of private property,
33
Philip Pettit, ‘The Republican Constitution’ in Eoin Carolan (ed), The Constitution of Ireland: Perspectives and Prospects
(Bloomsbury Professional 2012) 42-3.
34
Liam Murphy and Thomas Nagel, The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice (Oxford UP 2002) 8, 31-2.
35
JW Singer and JM Beermann, ‘The Social Origins of Property’ (1993) 6 Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence 217.
36
ibid 229.
37
Pistor (n 10) 78-80.
38
Howlin (n 23) 70.
39
Morris Cohen, ‘Property and Sovereignty’ (1927-1928) 13 Cornell Law Quarterly 8, 8.
40
Yun-chien Chang and Henry E Smith, ‘An Economic Analysis of Civil versus Common Law Property’ (2012) 88 Notre
Dame Law Review 1.
41
Cohen (n 39) 12.
42
Walsh (n 20) 236.
43
Howlin (n 23) 2-3.
44
Underkuffler (n 30) 1044.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
30
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
evolving from the Anglo-American enlightenment and associated with the classical liberal
tradition. While embracing the progressive theory of property, Underkuffler does speak for
the putative benefits of personal property for psychological development. O’Donnell cites
Underkuffler in this respect and sets out some of the other aspects of the liberal viewpoint,
which he sees as being contained in the Irish Constitution:
at the core of the right to private property, in common with all personal
rights, is the right to be let alone’, a zone of personal freedom. [...]
[Regarding Underkuffler’s psychological development point] This approach
is of a piece with James Madison’s understanding of the importance of
property: not for personal acquisitiveness, but rather as a guarantor of liberty
and thus of every other right.
45
This liberal idea of property rights characterises property as providing a robust level of
private authority to individuals, thereby allowing for enhanced autonomy and the ability to
plan one's future.
46
Property protects the individual from encroachments by a potentially
tyrannical state and also provides security from dependency on that State.
47
Intertwined with
this perspective historically are certain moral and economic claims. The moral claim
according to Locke is that a person acquires property through mixing their labour with it. It
follows that property is just desert for labour.
48
State interference with these rights is
presumed to be unjustified unless a sufficient justification is given.
Numerous economic justifications are also associated with the liberal viewpoint, some
reaching back to Aristotle. These include that private property encourages improvement of
the things to which the property rights relate, a justification that extends to intellectual
property rights as reward for ingenuity.
49
If an individual does not have the certainty of
ownership of an object into the future, why would she improve it?
50
The classical liberal
vision of property also emphasises that property serves to coordinate market interactions in
a tried and tested way.
51
In the context of the collapse of the USSR, Sunstein provided a modern reiteration of the
liberal position on property rights in a piece that encouraged the emerging new nations to
constitutionalise those rights.
52
The piece repeats some of the justifications referenced above,
such as property providing security against dependency on the state. On the above counts,
there is little disagreement with communitarians who, in the main, do not propose abolition
of property rights but only their regulation and/or reconfiguration to promote the common
good. Sunstein then lays out a strong liberal apologia for minimal state interference in
property rights:
[O]ne of the best ways to destroy a democratic system is to ensure that the
distribution of wealth and resources is unstable and constantly vulnerable to
45
O’Donnell (n 2) 428.
46
Hanoch Dagan, A Liberal Theory of Property (Cambridge University Press 2021) 1-3
47
See Jeremy Waldron, ‘Property and Ownership’ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer edn, 2020)
<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/property/> accessed 2 January 2022.
48
David Miller, ‘Justice and Property’ (1980) 22 Ratio 1, 5-7.
49
See TW Merrill, ‘The Demsetz Thesis and the Evolution of Property Rights’ (2002) 31 Journal of Legal Studies 331, 332.
50
Dagan (n 46) 5.
51
For a contrary view, i.e., that property is a form of monopoly that impedes the functioning of efficient markets, see EA
Posner and E Glen Weyl, Radical Markets: Uprooting Capitalism and Democracy for a Just Society (Princeton UP 2018).
52
Cass R. Sunstein, 'On Property and Constitutionalism' (1992) 14 Cardozo Law Review 907.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
31
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
reevaluation [sic] by the political process. A high degree of stability is
necessary to allow people to plan their affairs, to reduce the effects of
factional or interest group power in government, to promote investment, and
to prevent the political process from breaking down by attempting to resolve
enormous, emotionally laden issues about who is entitled to what.
53
The power of Sunstein’s argument is that it not only applies to actions such as compulsory
acquisition of property at full market value by the State, but also warns against any
interference in long-recognised property rights for fear of disrupting the stability on which a
society depends.
Liberals tend to favour a property system containing minimal restrictions on the ability of
persons to transfer their property rights in a market.
54
Their justifications here, to a large
extent, dovetail with the views of the law and economics scholars. The latter tend to promote
and justify property rights, and minimal state interference therewith, through the application
of concepts from the field of Neoclassical microeconomics.
55
It is notable that critiques of
the law and economics approach have come from perspectives aligned with
communitarianism, progressive property theory and republicanism.
56
This is relevant as, for
reasons discussed below, the communitarian tradition in Ireland is intertwined with
republicanism.
Perhaps the most significant modern defence of the liberal position is Dagans A Liberal
Theory of Property, a text that, interestingly, asserts a liberal theory far more sensitive to
communitarian concerns than, say, Sunstein's above.
57
Dagan admits that the challenge of
justifying property is 'much heavier and much more pressing than its friends take it to be'
since the existence of the current private property regime creates vulnerabilities for many
groups of people.
58
Dagan follows the liberal tradition of understanding private property as
power-conferring for individuals and therefore promoting of self-authorship and self-
determination.
59
However, he is also open to a property regime that restricts the rights of
property in 'means of production', as private authority over such resources means significant
power over the preferences of others.
60
He favours a background regime to property that
ensures everyone is entitled to own some autonomy-enhancing property, an idea with
politically social-democratic connotations.
61
Ultimately, of course, Dagan is a liberal thinker.
He views property rights interacting with markets as 'empowering' and argues that State
interference in property,
62
if required, ought to be undertaken gradually.
63
Thus, in contrast to the communitarians, liberals emphasise the importance of certainty of
property rights for a society to function properly and to achieve economic success.
53
ibid 916.
54
Margaret Jane Radin, 'The Liberal Conception of Property: Cross Currents in the Jurisprudence of Takings' (1988) 88
Columbian Law Review 1667, 1667.
55
See Amy Sinden, ‘The Tragedy of the Commons and the Myth of Private Property Solution’ (2007) 78 University of
Colorado Law Review 533.
56
Jane B Baron and Jeffrey L Dunoff, ‘Against Market Rationality: Moral Critiques of Economic Analysis in Legal Theory’
(1995) 17 Cardozo Law Review 431, 454-7.
57
Dagan (n 46).
58
ibid 243.
59
ibid 1-3.
60
ibid 42. 102.
61
ibid 42.
62
ibid 185.
63
ibid 213.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
32
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
The Irish Constitutional Position
Origin of the Constitution
As discussed above, the Irish Constitution possesses both communitarian and liberal aspects.
On the liberal side, for example, the courts have interpreted the Constitution as providing
for a strong separation of powers and strong criminal trial rights.
64
Regarding the property
clauses however, it will be argued that the Constitution falls squarely at the communitarian
end of the values spectrum. This will be done, first, by analysing the text of the Constitution
itself and secondly, by reference to case law. Irish courts have not always interpreted the
property clauses to give effect to communitarian values but, on the whole, they have
increasingly recognised the communitarian basis of the property clauses and have adjudicated
accordingly.
As Walsh clarifies with respect to her work, the purpose of delving into the history of the
constitutional property clauses is not to assert an 'originalist' reading of the Constitution but
to attempt to resolve some of the ambiguity within the meaning of the text itself.
65
The
following section engages with the history of the constitutional wording to elucidate the
intended meaning of the constitutional property clauses. Clarifying the origin of the
constitutional property clauses should aid judges when interpreting those clauses. It is not
intended to close off other aids to interpretation.
Historical scholarship shows that Archbishop John Charles McQuaid had a considerable
influence on drafting Article 43 of the Constitution, along with Article 45 which was
originally intended to accompany Article 43.
66
Correspondence between McQuaid and de
Valera clarifies that the former was reading the papal encyclicals Quadragesimo Anno and Rerum
Novarum when providing the latter with draft clauses.
67
Where passages from the encyclicals
are placed side by side with Articles 43 and 45, the parallels are striking.
68
Quadragesimo Anno explicitly dealt with the subject of private property. While it is true that
the encyclical defended private property against socialist movements which were perceived
as a threat to the institution, Walsh perhaps slightly over-emphasises liberal influence on the
encyclicals.
69
By quoting McDonagh’s argument that the Catholic Church’s strong anti-
communism influenced the encyclicals and therefore the Constitution,
70
Walsh does not
emphasise the anti-liberal message of Quadragesimo Anno.
71
The document contains multiple
denunciations of liberal private property and the economic system that it undergirds,
including the following:
64
See, for example, David Gwynn Morgan, The Separation of Powers in the Irish Constitution (Round Hall 1997).
65
Walsh (n 20) 45-6.
66
Dermot Keogh and Andrew McCarthy, The Making of the Irish Constitution 1937: Bunreacht na hÉireann (Mercier 2007) 117.
67
ibid 108.
68
ibid 117-8. Ultimately, concerns about litigants attempting to sue the state on the basis of the highly communitarian
Article 45 'Directive Principles of Social Policy' led to their removal from the cognisance of the courts. However, Walsh
has argued that, in balancing the values contained in Article 43, Article 45 could be a useful aid for courts. She refers to a
number of cases which provide something of a wedge to bring the principles partially back into judicial cognisance including
Attorney General v Paperlink [1984] ILRM 373 and Re Article 26 and Part V of the Planning and Development Bill 1999 [2000] 2 IR
321. The Indian Constitution explicitly borrowed the wording of many of the Article 45 principles and was amended to
prohibit judicial review of any legislation in furtherance of the principles. In an Indian case to be discussed below, the court
cited the principles in a communitarian ruling; an indication of possible success from another jurisdiction of Walsh’s
argument in favour of Article 45. See Walsh (n 20) and Allen (n 11) 47.
69
Walsh (n 20) 61.
70
Enda McDonagh, ‘Philosophical-Theological Reflections on the Constitution’ in Frank Litton (ed), The Constitution of
Ireland 1937-1987 (Institute of Public Administration 1988) 192.
71
Walsh (n 20) 75.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
33
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
Property, that is, 'capital,' has undoubtedly long been able to appropriate too
much to itself. Whatever was produced, whatever returns accrued, capital
claimed for itself, hardly leaving to the worker enough to restore and renew
his strength. […] It is true, indeed, that things have not always and
everywhere corresponded with this sort of teaching of the so-called
Manchesterian Liberals; yet it cannot be denied that economic social
institutions have moved steadily in that direction.
72
In contrast to the liberal vision of property, Pius XI promulgated a vision of ownership with
a twofold character, individual and social.
73
With respect to the social dimension, people
had to consider not only their own interests and desires but also those of the common good.
In terms of defining the duties property holders had in relation to the common good, the
State had the primary role.
74
Reflecting Thomism, the encyclical states that the law of social justice prohibits the exclusion
of one part of society from the wealth produced by society as a whole.
75
The superflua
discussed above also appear and the text states that a person’s superfluous income is not left
wholly to his own free determination.
76
The rich are instead bound to practice almsgiving,
beneficence, and munificence. While the emphasis here may be on individuals themselves
redistributing some of their resources, in the context of the document's overall emphasis on
public authority, the implication is that the State is sanctioned to undertake redistribution of
property.
Beyond the evidence for the direct influence of Quadragesimo Anno on the text, during the
parliamentary debates over the new Constitution, de Valera again reflected the encyclical’s
philosophy in his response to opposition TDs,
77
including the future Taoiseach, and barrister,
John A. Costello. Far from understanding the property clauses as a classic first generation
statement of liberal, civil and political rights, in the words of O’Donnell,
78
the contemporary
opposition feared Article 43 had the potential to enable a future left-wing government to
carry out property confiscation without compensation.
79
De Valera strongly rejected this
contention and explicitly referred to the dual character of property, individual and social, an
idea directly derived from Quadragesimo Anno.
80
Even while robustly defending Article 43
from accusations of being communist-friendly, de Valera strongly emphasised the social
aspect of property rights, reiterated their subjection to the common good, and emphasised a
natural law understanding of property rights.
81
Two prominent churchmen who had some influence on the drafting of the property clauses
in varying ways, Father Edward Cahill and Father Alfred O’Rahilly, felt the clauses did not
sufficiently reflect Catholic social teaching, mainly because they feared the legal class’s
education in the British legal tradition would lead to a liberal interpretation of the
72
Encyclical of Pius XI, Quadragesimo Anno <https://www.vatican.va/content/pius-
xi/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_19310515_quadragesimo-anno.html> accessed 2 January 2022, para 54.
73
ibid [45].
74
ibid [49].
75
ibid [57].
76
ibid [50].
77
Anthony Coughlan, ‘The Constitution and Social Policy’ in Frank Litton (ed), The Constitution of Ireland 1937-1987 (Institute
of Public Administration 1988) 154.
78
O’Donnell (n 2) 429.
79
Dáil Deb 12 May 1937, vol 67, col 210.
80
Dáil Deb 11 May 1937, vol 67, col 171.
81
Dáil Deb 13 May 1937, vol 67, col 215.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
34
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
Constitution. Cahill wrote that individualistic and Liberal [sic] principles of English
jurisprudenceinfluenced many Irish lawyers and there was a real danger that the intentions
of the Constitution would thereby be frustrated.
82
Hogan argues that Cahill was prescient
in this view and that courts have somewhat adopted an individual-centred approach to
property rights.
83
Cahill’s anxiety over the ability of legal minds to understand the meaning
of the language of Article 43.2 should serve to remind those legal minds of the philosophical
basis for Article 43.2 rather than absolving them of their responsibility to properly construe
the text simply because judges have failed to do so on previous occasions. As Walsh notes,
judges are mandated by the Constitution to engage with the communitarian values of Article
43.2; it is not an optional exercise.
84
The connection between Article 43, Quadragesimo Anno and Thomist philosophy has long
been recognised by commentators.
85
Mr Justice Brian Walsh, writing extrajudicially, opined
that the Constitution reflected almost perfectly the Thomistic conception of property
discussed above. Indeed, his understanding of Irish constitutional property rights mirrors the
values of the progressive property theorists in the US and their emphasis on the obligations
of property rights holders:
The starting point must be a philosophical concept of what are property
rights. [...] Nobody is given the right to accumulate property and retain it and
to assert that right against the requirements of social justice. [...] Strictly
speaking one cannot claim as of right more property than one requires for
one’s own support. While the right of private property exists in the interests
of the common good it is subordinate to the common good. [...] The
reference in Article 43 Section 1, to maoin tsaoghalta or external goods, in
contrast to goods of the body and goods of the soul, provides the clue to
the philosophy in question. These were the ideas of St Thomas Aquinas.
86
Mr Justice Brian Walsh went on in the same passage to contrast the Thomistic philosophy
of Irish constitutional property law with both the absolutism of the French Civil Code and
the common law’s orientation in favour of property rights.
87
If Mr Justice Brian Walsh’s
contention that the values of Irish constitutional jurisprudence on property rights are
Thomist is correct then it follows that property rights that protect the material security of
human beings are worthy of greater protection than property rights that protect returns on
investment; a position for which there is some authority (as discussed later). However, while
Thomism is undoubtedly an influence on the values to be applied to constitutional property
rights in Ireland, it would be a stretch to argue that Thomism must be the sole metric with
which to evaluate such rights.
88
Commentators sympathetic to a liberal viewpoint of the Constitution, not finding Article 43
conducive, often turn to Article 40.3.2° instead. Judges have also found the simpler wording
of Article 40.3.2° more attractive than the tortured syntax of Article 43.
89
Article 40.3.2°
appeared to be an avenue for the entrance of liberal values into constitutional adjudication
82
Gerard Hogan, The Origins of the Irish Constitution, 1928-1941 (Royal Irish Academy 2012) 573.
83
ibid 96.
84
Walsh (n 20) 183.
85
See Walsh (n 21).
86
Brian Walsh (n 2) 148.
87
ibid.
88
Walsh (n 20).
89
Ronan Keane, ‘Land Use, Compensation and the Community’ (1983) 18 Irish Jurist 23, 32.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
35
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
of property rights. However, as was pointed out in Moynihan v Greensmyth, even the State
protection of property from unjust attack in Article 40.3.2° is qualified by the words as
best it may which implies circumstances in which the State may have to balance its
protection of the right as against other obligations from regard for the common good.
90
Walsh highlights the fact that where State protection of property rights from 'unjust attack'
has been centred by judges, Article 43 values have been marginalised.
91
In the context of commonwealth constitutions, Allen has written about what might be
termed liberalism creep, a phenomenon where post-colonial states chose to imbue their new
constitutions with communitarian values but where courts at a national and commonwealth
level have handed down judgments that favoured individual rights over those of the
community.
92
The most prominent example of this occurred in India where the Supreme
Court struck down legislation that provided for graduated scales of compensation for
compulsory acquisition of lands from the aristocratic zamindar class.
93
The legislature
responded with constitutional change and the courts were forced to compromise. Allen
discusses the relationship between ownership of property and political power and argues that
the preference judiciaries in post-colonial states have historically had for individuals over
communities created a 'real risk' that those communities could be deprived 'of their capacity
to define their common identity' and their ability to enrich their own lives having fought to
achieve independence.
94
The Land Question
As discussed earlier, there has been a failure by courts and commentators to even attempt to
understand the meaning of Article 43’s wording despite its clear origin in Catholic social
teaching. An aspect of this failure, arguably, has been the further failure to situate
constitutional property rights in their historical context, particularly in relation to the
historical land question in Ireland.
95
The connection between the political battle over ownership of land in Ireland and
constitutional property rights is clear. Mr Justice Walsh extrajudicially opined that judicial
approaches to property rights have been 'conditioned by history and the land struggle'.
96
Prior
to Mr Justice Walsh, JM Kelly had enquired as to how certain conservative commentators’
views on constitutional property rights could be reconciled with the compulsorily purchase
and redistribution of land carried out through the Land Acts.
97
Wylie describes the stages through which increasingly strong legislation led to the
redistribution of land from landlords to tenant farmers.
98
He further describes the evolving
role of the Land Commission in the process whereby the vast majority of Irish agricultural
land changed possession. Lyall describes how the Land Act 1881 was contemporaneously
denounced as an infringement of landlords’ property rights as it required a landlord to
compensate a tenant for disturbing his occupancy and to compensate him further for
90
[1977] IR 55 (SC) 70.
91
Walsh (n 20) 95.
92
Allen (n 11) 109-110.
93
ibid 49-53.
94
ibid 110.
95
See John Cleland Wylie, Wylie on Irish Land Law (6th edn, Bloomsbury Professional 2020) ch 1.45-1.56.
96
Brian Walsh, ‘Foreword’ in James O’Reilly and Mary Redmond (eds), Cases and Materials on the Irish Constitution
(Incorporated Law Society of Ireland 1980) xx-xi.
97
John Maurice Kelly, Fundamental Rights in the Irish Law and Constitution (2nd edn, Allen Figgis and Co 1967) 173.
98
Wylie (n 95) ch 1.45-1.56.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
36
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
improvements made to the property.
99
Later Acts, including those introduced during the Free
State period and following the introduction of the Constitution, granted the Land
Commission very significant powers to intervene in property rights.
100
Wylie very directly
sees the history of increasing State intervention in property as informing the 1937
Constitution.
101
Indeed, senior civil servants were worried about the prospect that
constitutional property rights could allow challenges to the work of the Land Commission,
a very practical concern in 1937 when the Commission continued to transform Irish land-
holdings.
102
In cases such as Fisher v Land Commission
103
and Foley v Land Commission,
104
the social
importance of the Land Acts and Land Commission was recognised. Fisher involved a
challenge to the Land Acts which argued it was unconstitutional that the Acts did not bestow
a right of appeal to the courts following expropriation of land by the Land Commission from
a tenant. The land could be re-occupied by the Land Commission on the basis of one of a
number of reasons listed in the 1939 Act, including for the improvement or rearrangement
of a land holding. While the decisions of the High Court and Supreme Court would now be
considered bad law given the evolution of separation of powers and fair procedures, their
recognition of the significance of the Land Question is of note. The High Court stated that
the main object of the legislation must have been the 'common weal' in the form of relief for
'small holders struggling with uneconomic farms'.
105
The Court stated further:
the Legislature (i) conceived that the public interest demanded a more
equitable distribution of certain estates, involving the curtailment or the total
expropriation of some proprietors to minister to the land hunger of the
afflicted smaller people; (ii) saw that, whatever compensation might be paid,
public policy alone could justify the necessary interference with lawful rights
of property in land […].
106
The Supreme Court echoed the above, stating that the 'main task' of the Land Commission
was the creation of a 'peasant proprietorship of a certain standard'.
107
The words of the High
Court above were stated by Gavan Duffy J, the same judge who would go on to give the
ruling in Buckley v Attorney General,
108
a judgment considered to be much less deferential to
the Oireachtas on the matter of property rights and of separation of powers. Gavan Duffy J
refers to the 'land hunger of the afflicted smaller people', a phrase that echoes the famine
period and shows the continuing resonance of the Land Question in the 1940s. This suggests
that while the courts were not willing to allow the legislature deprive citizens of their property
rights for political motives and without fair procedures, as had occurred in Buckley, they were
willing to defer to the legislature on property rights when the legislation in question had clear
and recognisable social goals. Another case involving a challenge to the powers of the Land
99
Howlin (n 23) 375.
100
These included the Land Law (Commission) Act 1923 during the Free State era and the Land Acts 1933, 1936 and 1939;
the 1936 and 1939 Acts being introduced by the Oireachtas in response to certain judicial decisions that affected the power
of the Land Commission. See Brendan Edgeworth, ‘Rural Radicalism Restrained: The Irish Land Commission and the
Courts (1933-39)’ (2007) 42 Irish Jurist 1.
101
Wylie (n 95) ch 1.61.
102
Hogan (n 82) 327.
103
[1948] IR 3.
104
[1952] IR 118. (SC).
105
Fisher (n 103) 10
106
ibid.
107
ibid 26.
108
[1950] IR 67.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
37
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
Commission, Foley, chose to follow Fisher and to distinguish Buckley. The Supreme Court in
that case referred to the Land Acts as a very important branch of our social legislation.
109
The more recent case of Shirley v A. O'Gorman & Co Ltd provides further evidence of the
courts’ recognition of the historical significance of land in Ireland when determining
questions of property rights.
110
Shirley concerned a challenge to legislation which allowed
tenants in business premises to buy out the ground rent from their landlord in some instances
at prices only one eighth of market value. The High Court rejected the challenge and in doing
so stated that it was entitled to consider 'the social history of the country' in order to provide
context to the challenged legislation.
111
The social history in question here was that of the
Land Question and the redistribution it brought about from the land-owning class to the
tenant class. This context was required in determining whether the legislature had social
justice in mind when passing said legislation. Peart J concluded that social justice had been a
significant factor for the legislature, and this was crucial in his rejection of the constitutional
challenge.
112
Complementarily, other scholars have emphasised how the Land Question must be
understood against the colonial context of Irish history. As suggested by Walsh above,
113
understanding that context is crucial for understanding why property rights in an Irish
context are to be distinguished from Britain and the United States. Allen has described how
former colonies who became members of the commonwealth chose to place different
emphases on property rights, usually of a communitarian nature, than their colonisers.
114
Walsh and Fox O’Mahony argue for the existence of a unique Irish conception of property
in contrast to Britain, centring the idea of property as security;
115
a point further discussed
below. So at variance with Britain was the Irish experience of property rights that the first
draft constitution for the Irish Free State put forward by Cumann na nGaedheal contained
a property rights provision that was influenced by a Soviet constitution with the 'Soviet
character' of the property clauses being a factor in its rejection by London.
116
The fact that it
was put forward in the first place by what became Ireland’s staple centre-right party illustrates
how the independence struggle shaped the Irish understanding of property rights.
It is unsurprising that a country like Ireland with a colonial history intimately tied to the Land
Question would choose to place a different emphasis on property rights than certain other
common law jurisdictions. While Irish law remains based on the common law, the
Constitution is the exact place to pursue general modifications of the common law. The
Constitution's preamble itself centres the struggle for independence.
The political ideology which framed that anti-colonial struggle was republicanism and its
influence can also be seen on the Constitution.
117
In reformulating land law through the Law
and Conveyancing Law Reform Act 2009, the Law Reform Commission justified changes to
109
Foley (n 104) 153.
110
[2006] IEHC 27.
111
ibid.
112
ibid.
113
See 'Origin of the Constitution' section above.
114
Allen (n 11) 109-110.
115
Rachael Walsh and Lorna Fox O’Mahony, ‘Land Law, Property Ideologies and the British-Irish Relationship’ (2018) 47
Common Law World Review 7, 23.
116
ibid 18. See also Thomas Mohr, ‘British Involvement in the Creation of the First Irish Constitution’ (2008) 30 Dublin
University Law Journal 166
117
McDonagh (n 70) 197-8; Coughlan (n 77) 145.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
38
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
common law property rules on the basis of the republican character of the State.
118
Indeed,
Daly has argued for republicanism as the solution to the falling away of natural law as an
'underlying public philosophy' of the Constitution.
119
As judges must necessarily interpret the
Constitution against some set of values, given that value-free interpretation is impossible for
a document that expressly mandates the courts to balance various principles against each
other, Daly argues that republicanism holds the most appropriate set of values.
120
Republicanism is easily reconciled with communitarian property theory as the republican
conception of freedom is as freedom from domination, as opposed to the liberal conception
of freedom as freedom from interference.
121
Freedom from domination accords, for
example, with property as material security more so than with property as a vehicle for the
pursuit of profit.
Whatever the political potential of the constitutional property provisions, the evolution of
case law has bounded that potential in particular ways. The point about the influence of
republicanism and anti-colonialism, however, does complement both the importance of the
Land Question in the Irish constitutional constellation and, ultimately, the communitarian
character of the constitutional property rights provisions. The Land Question context reveals
the extent to which the Constitution envisages the possibility for comprehensive
redistribution and reconfiguration of property rights.
Blake-Madigan A Threat to Communitarian Property Jurisprudence
The relationship between Articles 40.3.2° and 43 is critical for determining whether the
Constitution leans communitarian or liberal on property rights since the Constitution’s
communitarian content emanates from Article 43 with its references to 'social justice' and
the 'exigencies of the common good'. The courts’ position on the relationship has
continuously changed over the years with many judgments contradicting each other often
without one expressly overruling another.
122
While it appeared at one point that 40.3.2° might
predominate in constitutional interpretation, the communitarian values of 43 have re-
emerged as a crucial component in constitutional property rights adjudication.
Many early cases in Irish constitutional property jurisprudence ruled that the property rights
comprehended by Article 40.3.2° were those listed in Article 43.
123
The question of the
relationship between these articles appeared to be definitively answered in Blake-Madigan,
124
a
case involving a challenge to rent control legislation, where the ruling on the relationship
between Articles 43 and 40.3.2° was to the detriment of the former and the communitarian
values contained therein.
125
Blake-Madigan has never been expressly overruled and many of
its rulings continue to cast a shadow of doubt over how the legislature can constitutionally
intervene in property rights.
126
118
Law Reform Commission, Consultation Paper on Reform and Modernisation of Land Law and Conveyancing Law (LRC CP 34
2004) 34.
119
Daly (n 5) 91.
120
ibid 104-6.
121
Pettit (n 33) 40.
122
Hogan and others, Kelly: The Irish Constitution (5th edn, Bloomsbury Professional 2018) ch 7.8.
123
See Foley (n 104) and Attorney General v Southern Industrial Trust [1960] 94 ILTR 161.
124
Blake v Attorney General [1982] IR 117 (SC).
125
Gerard McCormack, ‘Blake-Madigan and Its Aftermath’ (1983) Dublin University Law Journal 205, 224.
126
See Hilary Hogan and Finn Keyes, ‘The Housing Crisis and the Constitution’ (2021) 65 Irish Jurist 87, 89.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
39
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
The facts in Blake-Madigan involved a particularly extreme infringement of the plaintiffs’
property rights.
127
The legislation in question imposed rent control to the extent that rent
was between nine and nineteen times less than the market rate. Combined with onerous
obligations to repair the premises in question and strong protections for tenants from
eviction, the plaintiffs argued that the legislation effectively rendered their properties of no
financial benefit. O’Higgins CJ stated that the Constitution offered a 'double protection' for
property, a general guarantee that the State could not abolish private property as per Article
43.1 and a protection for individuals that their specific items of property would be protected
as per Article 40.3.2°.
128
This interpretation would have made Article 40.3.2° the clause of
real importance and effectively side-lined Article 43 values almost entirely from adjudication.
The court went on to rule that, as the legislation affected the plaintiffs’ property rights and
as it did so without justifying why this particular group of individuals were being singled out,
i.e. persons who happened to have property rights in rent-controlled dwellings, it constituted
an unjust attack.
129
The means of the tenants in question or of the landlords were not factors
in the legislation nor did the legislation provide any compensatory factor to the landlords for
the interference in their property. The rent control provisions were therefore
unconstitutional. The court did not explicitly rule on the recovery of possession aspect of
the legislation. It acknowledged restriction of landlords’ rights in that respect could be
justified in certain circumstances but as those restrictions were part of a legislative package
with unconstitutional elements in this instance, the whole legislation must fall together.
130
The case concluded by gently pointing out that the legislature should protect the tenants in
question by passing new legislation that would determine fair rents and provide for a degree
of security of tenure.
131
The Bill proposed by the legislature to fill this lacuna was referred to the Supreme Court by
the President under Article 26 of the Constitution and the resulting judgment appeared to
further cement the Blake-Madigan decision itself. The Bill envisaged a period where tenants
would pay a higher rent each year until, after five years, they would be paying market value.
132
The court ruled that market value rent was the 'just and proper rent' and found the bill
unconstitutional on the same basis as Blake-Madigan; that it constituted an unjust attack on
the plaintiffs’ property rights without justification.
133
On the face of it, the Article 26 case
appears to enshrine a right to market rent.
134
Christman points out that granting full income
rights such as the right to receive market rent would amount to allowing full bilateral trades
with no regulation, taxation or interference.
135
It would preclude any regulation by the State
that related to the distribution of resources and would thus infringe upon state sovereignty.
Cohen further argues that property rights as a guarantee to investors of a return on their
investment is akin to the State guaranteeing private actors a percentage of the value produced
by society as a whole; a position clearly at odds with a communitarian constitutional
jurisprudence.
136
127
Blake-Madigan (n 124) 132.
128
ibid 135.
129
ibid 136-40.
130
ibid 140.
131
ibid 142.
132
[1983] IR 181 (SC).
133
ibid 190.
134
Walsh (n 20) 142-3.
135
John Christman, ‘Distributive Justice and the Complex Structure of Ownership’ (1994) 23 Philosophy & Public Affairs
225.
136
Cohen (n 39) 13.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
40
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
A short number of years later, however, the same Chief Justice who had given the ruling in
Blake-Madigan gave a judgment in O’Callaghan v Commissioners of Public Works that contained
an altogether different approach.
137
In doing so, he was influenced by the intermittent
judgment in Dreher v Irish Land Commission, a case where the Land Commission carried out a
compulsory purchase for monies marginally below market value.
138
Walsh J had stated in
Dreher that any State action authorised by Article 43 could not by definition be unjust for the
purposes of Article 40.3.2°.
139
The plaintiff in O’Callaghan had claimed legislation which allowed the Commissioners of
Public Works to make a preservation order protecting a national monument on his land
without providing him with compensation was unconstitutional. The Supreme Court ruled
the plaintiff was not entitled to compensation. Referring to Blake-Madigan, the court disagreed
with the role in constitutional property rights to which that case had consigned Article 43. It
stated that Article 43 did more than merely institutionalise private property.
140
It authorises
the State to regulate the exercise of the property rights referenced in that article. When the
question of an unjust attack on a property right was raised, Articles 43 and 40.3.2° ought to
be read together so as to give effect, in so far as possible, to both provisions.
141
This position was generally followed thereafter with the ruling in Dreher emphasised, that is,
if a piece of legislation conforms to Article 43 then it is necessarily constitutional for the
purposes of 40.3.2°.
142
In more recent years, the relationship between the Articles has been
summarised as that they 'mutually inform each other'.
143
It is important to therefore note
that, since Dreher implicitly overruled the Supreme Court's interpretation of Article 43 in
Blake-Madigan, if a case with the same facts were being decided today then courts would have
to apply different considerations, i.e. it would have to apply communitarian values to the
legislation.
Moreover, the Article 26 case was intimately related to Blake-Madigan itself and cannot be
read without the aid of the latter judgment. The Oireachtas’ bill sought to legislate as Blake-
Madigan had suggested; to protect the now precarious tenants in question by providing for
'fair' rents. The Article 26 case seemed to then rule that the only fair rent was market rent.
Such a contradiction may be resolved by looking to the fact the Article 26 judgment again
reiterated that no justification was provided for why property owners of rent-controlled
dwellings should, in particular, be subjected to infringements of their rights. If no such
justification was provided and no reference to the circumstances of the tenants was made,
then the court could perhaps only conclude there was no reason why market rent would not
be the assumed rent. It is arguable, therefore, that where a better justification is provided by
the Oireachtas for why it seeks to diverge from market rent as the norm and, in light of
Dreher, especially where issues of social justice and the common good arise, courts should
not apply the logic shown by the Supreme Court in the Article 26 case. Courts have not
applied such logic in practice, and this further indicates that these cases should be seen as
results produced by unique sets of facts and a unique application of the law, focusing only
137
[1985] ILRM 364 (SC).
138
[1984] ILRM 94 (SC).
139
ibid 96.
140
Blake-Madigan (n 124) 367.
141
ibid.
142
See, inter alia, ESB v Gormley [1985] IR 129 (SC) 150; Lawlor v Minister for Agriculture [1990] 1 IR 356 (HC) 373; Clancy v
Ireland [1988] IR 326 (HC) 336; Murphy v GM [2001] 4 IR 113 (SC) 157; Re Article 26 and the Health (Amendment) Bill 2004
[2005] 1 IR 105 (SC) 200.
143
J & J Haire v Minister for Health [2010] 2 IR 615 (HC) 644 quoting JM Kelly: The Irish Constitution (4th edn, Lexis Nexis
2003) 1993. The same language was used in Flynn v Breccia [2015] IEHC 547 [246].
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
41
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
on Article 40.3.2°. The rent control cases therefore represent a road not travelled for the
courts and a road now cut off by further developments.
An argument might be made that the Constitution’s placement of property rights alongside
such liberal rights as freedom of assembly in Article 40 connotes a liberal understanding.
While this argument may have some merit, like the other rights contained therein, the rights
associated with liberalism contained in Article 40 have consistently been ruled not to be
absolute.
144
Article 40.3.2°, then, may simply be a guarantee that the Oireachtas, under the
disguise of a claim that they were promoting the common good, cannot unfairly and
disproportionately interfere with property rights.
145
Examples of such unfair and
disproportionate interferences may be seen in Brennan v Attorney General
146
and Daly v Revenue
Commissioners
147
where legislation produced demonstrably unfair tax results for individuals
without any social justification.
Even where cases appear to have had pro-property rights outcomes, communitarian values
have taken centre stage, for example in the Health Bill case (discussed below).
148
In Re Article
26 and the Employment Equality Bill 1996, the court held that the goal of equality in the
workplace did justify a delimitation of property rights via forcing employers to make their
workplaces more adequate for disabled employees.
149
The bill was ruled unconstitutional only
because it attempted to realise its goal by placing onerous burdens on employers, not taking
account of their respective means. Thus, the Court’s issue was with how the law applied, the
problem being with the unequal sharing of the burden rather than the existence of the burden
itself.
Neither has the proportionality doctrine ultimately impeded the realisation by the Oireachtas
of social justice and common good considerations through regulation of property rights.
While that doctrine will not be discussed in this article, it is important to point out that certain
commentators have argued that the doctrine had somewhat erased Article 43 values from
judicial discourse.
150
It is submitted that this outcome, although it had been a threat, did not
ultimately occur as some of the case law discussed in this section and later sections illustrate.
There is now consistency in that all constitutional property rights must be evaluated with
communitarian criteria in mind. While the property rights of individuals will also be given
due consideration, the spectre of liberalism creep denuding the communitarianism of Article
43,
151
which was arguably raised in the Blake-Madigan judgment, has largely been abated.
Liberal Aspects of Article 43
To evaluate the extent to which communitarian values predominate in Irish constitutional
property jurisprudence, it is important to also consider the possible liberal aspects of Article
43 and their potential to create a countervailing tendency. While 43.2 speaks of social justice,
the common good and the regulation of property rights in accordance with those principles,
43.1 states that the right to the ownership of external goods is a natural right, antecedent to
positive law. The concept of a natural right to the private ownership of external goods
144
E.g., in respect of freedom of expression. See Hogan and others (n122) paras 7.6.07 7.6.136.
145
Central Dublin Development Association v Attorney General [1975] 108 ILTR 69 (HC) 85.
146
[1984] ILRM 355 (SC).
147
[1995] 3 IR 1 (HC).
148
Re Article 26 and Health Bill (n 142).
149
[1997] 2 IR 321 (SC) 367-8.
150
Hogan (n 1) 377.
151
See McCormack (n 125) 224.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
42
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
appears at first sight to be a strong private property guarantee. Private ownership is placed
into the realm of natural rights and therefore outside the realm of political contestation.
In Blascaod Mór Teo, Budd J situated 43.1 in its historical context, stating that it connoted 'a
rejection of fascism and totalitarianism in the sense of recognising the right of the individual
to own property rather than the State owning all assets.'
152
This claim has some historical
basis in that de Valera’s government did not wish to be perceived as communist-friendly.
153
However, with further analysis, it can be seen that Article 43.1’s natural rights language is not
as strong of a property rights guarantee as it might first appear. The question of the natural
law conception of property returns the discussion to natural law philosophers such as
Aquinas who, as discussed earlier, do not necessarily have an absolutist perspective on private
property. A strict reading of the clause shows that it guarantees no more than that the general
rights to own objects and to transfer them may not be abolished. In a 1937 internal
memorandum, one of the Constitution's drafters, JJ McElligott, made the point that, on the
basis of the text alone, Article 43.1's wording was sufficiently general that it could
theoretically have allowed the State to prohibit the ownership of land.
154
In a more
contemporary context, Pettit made a similar point when he argued that Article 43 could only
be understood as a right to be able to own external goods under some system of positive law;
it did not impose any particular form on the ownership rights that the positive law was
required to establish.
155
Nevertheless, Article 43.1 does have certain liberal connotations. Blake-Madigan ruled that it
provided a general protection for the institution of private property.
156
By enumerating the
rights to transfer, inherit and bequeath property as further rights protected, the Constitution
to some extent separates from property rights, but provides protection to, rights to transfer
property associated with freedom of contract. By referencing both property and rights to
transfer it, the Constitution guarantees some form of a market in property. It could be argued
that Article 43.1 suggests, though does not necessitate, a property rights regime grounded on
liberal ideas of strong property rights and markets. The State’s ability to intervene in property
rights is thus to a certain extent bounded. In connotation at least, Sunstein would find much
to admire in this article.
While these liberal aspects of Article 43 should not be discounted, it is submitted that the
legislature has never approached the outer limits of its ability to intervene in the institution
of property as protected by Article 43.1. There has never been an attempt to abolish private
property and 43.1 has offered little practical value to litigants trying to protect their property
rights. Article 43.1 does, however, mandate that when judges apply Article 43.2 values in
adjudicating constitutional property rights, the liberal values in Article 43.1 must also be
considered.
Application of Communitarian Values
The below sub-sections relate to two areas where the courts have centred communitarian
values. The courts’ interpretation in these areas demonstrates the emerging dominance of
the communitarian tendency in constitutional property law.
152
[1998] IEHC 38.
153
See Walsh (n 19) 98.
154
Hogan (n 82) 513.
155
Pettit (n 33) 44.
156
Blake-Madigan (n 124) 135.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
43
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
Planning Law
In recent years, planning law generally has seen many judicial decisions which have applied
the communitarian values of Article 43. There has been no resolution but some evolution
on the question of whether planning law consists of an interference with property rights, an
enhancement of property rights, or whether planning permission is itself a species of
property right. For example, Central Dublin Development held planning legislation to be an
interference with property rights.
157
In two later cases, Re Article 26 and Part V of the Planning
and Development Bill 1999
158
and Pine Valley Developments v Minister for Environment,
159
the
Supreme Court took the opposite view and determined that planning permission was an
enhancement or enlargement of property rights. In the Part V case, the bill in question
required owners of land with development rights attached to it to cede 20% of that land to
local authorities for monies equivalent to existing use value as opposed to market value.
160
The bill’s aim as the provision of housing for people of moderate means in a housing context
where such people were increasingly excluded from purchasing property. The consideration
that planning permission enhanced property rights was crucial in reaching the
communitarian-friendly ruling that the bill was constitutional.
161
Pine Valley related to a challenge by a purchaser who made its purchase on the basis that an
outline of planning permission had been granted only for that planning permission to have
been deemed unlawfully granted in another Supreme Court decision.
162
The purchaser
claimed its property rights had been infringed by virtue of the latter decision but the court
rejected this argument on the basis that a grant of planning permission was an enhancement
of property rights. The diminution in value that occurred therefore only affected the
enhancement, not the property rights themselves.
In McGrath Limestone v An Bord Pleanála, a case where the plaintiff challenged a decision to
restrict its ability to use certain quarrying methods on its land, the High Court stated that
planning law extended the principles of tort law in that it provided that citizens had a stake
in how their community was developed and how that development was regulated.
163
In a
recent High Court case, Clonres CLG v An Bord Pleanála, the more communitarian position
was further asserted by the court which stated private property did not include a right to
develop one’s land:
The Constitution is a social contract - not a one-way offer.
Without taking from the principles of land law, we are all, at best, leaseholders
on Planet Earth. All property must be held with some view to the benefit of
society as a whole and of future generations, and is not to be dealt with as
one sees fit. Even the most self made Ayn-Randian entrepreneur draws
enormous benefits from her membership of society […] To argue that
society’s endeavours to ensure that outcome (through development plans,
for example) have to be read narrowly and restrictively, while the individual
157
Central Dublin Development (n 145).
158
Part V (n 68) 352.
159
[1987] IR 23 (SC) 45.
160
Re Article 26 and Part V (n 68) 324.
161
ibid 353.
162
Pine Valley (n 159).
163
[2014] IEHC 382 (HC) [10.5].
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
44
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
property owner can take the full advantage of societal provision both direct
and indirect, is to entirely distort the social contract.
164
Humphreys J’s above statement clearly reflects communitarian and republican values. The
judgment accords with progressive property theory and acknowledges that the existence of
property assumes a society and the institutions which protect property. It is strongly anti-
liberal while still recognising property rights. Nevertheless, the question of planning
permission's relationship to property rights has not been fully resolved as can be seen by, for
example, the judgment in Sister Mary Christian v Dublin City Council where the court favoured
the Central Dublin Development position that planning law curtails property rights.
165
In these recent cases, the Irish courts have, in a sense, approached planning law through the
prism of the normative aspect of property rather than through the descriptive aspect.
Assuming a particular set of property rights as inherent to property has the potential to create
a liberal bias in the normative evaluation of property rights due to the historical influence of
private actors on the concept of property.
166
However, this potential has been somewhat
limited by the principles articulated in Central Dublin Development which envisage State
intervention in property rights as routine, and property rights as far from absolute and not
requiring a very high bar to be met to justify State intervention.
167
Kenny J's judgment states
that the Irish constitutional position on property is that it was comprised of a bundle of
rights as opposed to one unified thing.
168
In an Irish constitutional context, there has been
no attempt to list the individual rights of this bundle. The most widely-used enumeration of
the bundle comes from Honoré
169
but even Honoré conceded that his bundle described a
certain western form of property.
170
Honoré recognised the political significance of property
rights
171
in a later essay explicitly arguing against Nozick’s libertarian theory of property rights
and for a system of redistribution by the State not dissimilar to that of Aquinas.
172
While
there is no doubt in practice that property in Ireland has not diverged substantially from
other western property rights systems, the centrality of communitarianism to the
constitutional undergirding of property in Ireland raises the possibility that in order to
determine what rights are included in the bundle in an Irish context, values must be part of
that discussion.
Property Rights Holders
A second area that reveals the communitarian understanding of property rights at the heart
of Irish constitutional jurisprudence is the recognition that the strength of property rights
can vary based on who holds those rights. This idea is intertwined with the idea of property
as corresponding to security. Christman posits that property rights relating to the material
security of the individual are deserving of greater protection than those relating to profit-
making.
173
164
[2021] IEHC 303 [84].
165
[2012] 2 IR 506 (HC) 561.
166
Pistor (n 10) 89-91.
167
Central Dublin Development (n 145) 85.
168
ibid.
169
Honoré’s standard incidents are the right to possess, the right to use, the right to manage, the right to the income of the
thing, the right to the capital, the right to security, the rights or incidents of transmissibility and absence of term, the
prohibition of harmful use, liability to execution, and the incident of residuary. Anthony Maurice Honoré, ‘Ownership’ in
Anthony Guest (ed), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence (Oxford UP 1961) 370.
170
Anthony Maurice Honoré, ‘Property, Title and Redistribution’ in Larry May and Jeff Brown (eds), Philosophy of Law:
Classical and Contemporary Readings (Wiley Blackwell 2010) 265.
171
Honoré (n 169) 372.
172
Honoré (n 170) 267-8.
173
Christman (n 135).
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
45
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
The question as to whether companies held constitutional property rights was not definitively
answered in the affirmative until Iarnród Éireann v Ireland which did not set out a
comprehensive reasoning as to why companies ought to have such rights.
174
Previous cases
had not recognised such rights, but indirectly protected property owned by companies by
virtue of protecting the property rights of shareholders. PMPS v Attorney General had held
that companies, as creatures of positive law, could not have constitutional property rights
under the Constitution as the property rights protected therein arose to 'man, in virtue of his
rational being'; the wording of Article 43.1.
175
Prior to Iarnród Éireann, the Constitution
Review Group had recommended that constitutional property rights should not be extended
to corporate persons.
176
The arguments put forward by those in the majority included the
contention that constitutional rights were intended to relate to human beings. They also
included the possibility that recognition of constitutional property rights of corporate
persons could mean corporate resources and financial power would be marshalled to
challenge the constitutionality of legislation and thereby have legal, financial and social
consequences.
177
Despite the ruling in Iarnród Éireann, there has been further judicial recognition that
constitutional rights may apply differently to human persons than to corporate persons. Kelly
cites the High Court cases of Digital Rights Ireland v Minister for Communications
178
and Smith v
Considine
179
as examples of this recognition but comments that the courts have not offered
any guidance as to how the rights may differ as between the categories.
180
Some indication of
how Irish courts factor in the differences in who holds property rights may be seen in Pine
Valley. Without specifying the exact causal relationship with its decision, the Supreme Court
placed a strong emphasis on the fact that the company’s investment was of a speculative and
commercial nature in its conclusion that no compensation was payable on foot of the
removal of the planning permission attached to the properties in question.
181
Re Article 26 and the Health Bill concerned proposed legislation that would retrospectively
declare lawful nursing home charges imposed without legal basis on elderly patients of
limited means.
182
The Supreme Court held the bill repugnant to the Constitution. It stated
that there was a moral quality to the right to ownership of property and this quality was
intimately related to the humanity of each individual.
183
The court proceeded to find that
property rights of persons of modest means must be particularly deserving of protection
since any abridgment of their rights would be proportionately more severe in its effects.
184
Decisions such as these illustrate that, despite the existence of constitutional property rights
for body corporates, the courts will not treat property rights as protection for profit-seeking
investments the same as property rights which serve the material security of human persons.
This is an area where Irish constitutional property rights jurisprudence demonstrates clear
174
[1996] 3 IR 321 (SC) 345-6.
175
[1983] IR 339 (HC) 349.
176
Constitution Review Group, Report of the Constitutional Review Group (Government of Ireland Stationery Office 1996) 364.
177
ibid 363.
178
[2010] IEHC 221 [51].
179
[2017] IEHC 22 [12].
180
Hogan (n 144) para 7.8.42.
181
Pine Valley (n 159) 46.
182
Re Article 26 and Health Bill (n 142) 200.
183
ibid 201-2.
184
ibid 201-2.
IRISH JUDICIAL STUDIES JOURNAL
46
[2023] Irish Judicial Studies Journal Vol 7(3)
communitarian values, whether or not the implications of these values have yet been fully
realised.
Conclusion
The Irish Constitution, as interpreted by case law, requires the Article 43.2 concepts of social
justice and the common good to be engaged with and applied by the courts when they
adjudicate on constitutional property rights. The meaning of these concepts must therefore
be given a proper analysis. This article has set out the normative theories of property with
the potential to assist with such an analysis and has used those theories to conduct the
analysis.
The genesis of the Irish constitutional provisions on property rights lies in the
communitarian teachings of the Catholic Church. The historical record shows the direct
influence of Church figures on the text and, indirectly through those figures, the influence
of papal encyclicals. The influence of Thomism has also been felt in Irish constitutional
property jurisprudence, an influence finding its way into that jurisprudence through the papal
encyclicals and Catholic social teaching generally. It is of note that these communitarian
influences are consistent with republicanism, a significant influence in the formation of the
Irish constitutional order. The Land Question discussion illustrates the objects envisaged by
these communitarian values: redistribution of property rights and reconfiguration of
property relationships. At least in respect of property rights, there is a strong argument that
these tendencies inform the underlying public philosophy of the Constitution.
While liberalism has a place in Irish constitutional jurisprudence generally, the spectre of
liberalism creep denuding the communitarian spirit of the Constitution with regard to
property rights has receded in recent years. Recent decisions in areas such as planning law
shows how the courts have increasingly centred communitarian values.
It may be concluded from this article as a whole that Irish constitutional property rights
jurisprudence possesses a relatively unambiguous theory of property rights. The
communitarian values of Article 43 provide a prism in determining the extent to which
property rights may be intervened in by the Oireachtas. Following some initial contradictory
currents in the case law, a consistent communitarianism in constitutional property rights
adjudication has recently been emerging. The analysis set out in this article corroborates the
validity of this emerging position.