Marshall University Marshall University
Marshall Digital Scholar Marshall Digital Scholar
Humanities Faculty Research Humanities
2014
Dreams as a Meta-Conceptual or Existential Experience Dreams as a Meta-Conceptual or Existential Experience
Jeremy Barris
Follow this and additional works at: https://mds.marshall.edu/humanities_faculty
Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Mind Commons
Abstract
The paper argues that dreams (or the recollected experience of dreams) consist partly in
an awareness or experience of the conceptual fabric of our existence. Since what we
mean by reality is intimately tied to the concepts given in our experience, dreams are
therefore also partly an awareness of the fabric of what we mean by being itself and in
general, that is, by objective as well as subjective reality. Further, the paper argues that
this characteristic of dreams accounts for several other, more specific aspects of dreams
and their possible interpretation, and that it allows us to see how these aspects are related
to each other. These more specific aspects are the peculiar types of conceptual or logical
relations and transitions that occur within dreams, dreams’ distinctive feeling texture, and
some dimensions of the grounds and nature of suitable methods of interpreting dreams.
Key words: dreams, logic, existential, feeling, dream interpretation
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
1
Dreams As a Meta-Conceptual or Existential Experience
Jeremy Barris
I shall try to show that dreams, or the recollected experience of dreams,
1
consist partly in
an awareness or experience of the conceptual fabric of our existence. Since what we
mean by reality is intimately tied to the concepts given in our experience, dreams are
therefore partly also an awareness of the fabric of what we mean by being itself and in
general, that is, by objective as well as subjective reality. To be clear, I am not reducing
dreams intellectualistically to concepts, but proposing that concepts themselves must be
understood as organic, inseparable aspects of substantial reality and life, and so also of
the feelings and images that occur in both our waking lives and our dreams.
I try to show, further, that this conceptual experience that partly characterizes
dreams accounts for several other, more specific aspects of dreams and their possible
interpretation, and allows us to see how these aspects are related to each other. These
more specific aspects are the peculiar types of conceptual or logical relations and
transitions that occur within dreams, dreams’ distinctive feeling texture, and some
dimensions of the grounds and nature of suitable methods of interpreting dreams.
1
Malcolm (1959) argued influentially that we cannot meaningfully refer to dreams
themselves. But see, for example, the essays revisiting his argument and defending this
possibility in Dunlop (1977).
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
2
1. Dreams As a Meta-Conceptual or Existential Experience
I have argued elsewhere that dreams consist partly in a movement or comparison between
views or interpretations of reality in general, or between understandings of the same
particular thing in terms of wholly incompatible sets of concepts (Barris, 2010). To
sketch that argument briefly here, one reason for thinking of dreams in this way is that we
can plausibly understand them as participating in the deep perplexities and
transformations that occur in waking life. In turn, we can plausibly understand these deep
transformations and perplexities as often involving a comparison or shift between
mutually exclusive general outlooks on things, or between mutually exclusive ways of
understanding the same concern in our lives.
2
So, for example, when I am depressed, the
whole world is bleak, and even positive events are experienced in the light of that
bleakness: they may make me feel, for instance, isolated in being unable to appreciate
them. But when I am contented with my life, even depressing events are experienced as
manageable and perhaps as background against which the good things of life stand out.
As Wittgenstein noted, ‘the world of the happy man is a different one from that of the
unhappy man,’ and in moving from one to the other it ‘becomes an altogether different
world’ (1961 [1921], p. 72, prop. 6.43).
2
That there are such mutually exclusive general outlooks or conceptual frameworks is
familiarly argued in philosophy of science (Feyerabend, 1993, especially chapter 16;
Kuhn, 1970; Wittgenstein, 1979), political philosophy (Lyotard, 1988 [1983]; MacIntyre,
1988; Taylor, 1985, especially chapters 3-5), and in discussions of the relations between
philosophical systems (Collingwood, 1940; Hall, 1960).
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
3
Again, as we mature, or undergo life crises, or come to appreciate perspectives or
cultural frameworks very different from our own, the values and priorities in terms of
which we make sense of our lives may change so that we can no longer identify with our
previous standpoint. The same events, things, and ways of conducting ourselves and
relating to others no longer have the same significance for us. For instance, being
assertive of our goals may strike us as a symptom of shamefully misunderstanding our
place in the world and of failing to appreciate the reality of others and of the
environment, where before it seemed to us to express an admirable and realistic
awareness of these same things.
Since we can plausibly understand dreams as participating in these shifts, it is at
least arguable, then, that the content of dreams often consists partly in a movement or
comparison between incompatible conceptual orders.
A second reason for thinking of dreams as in some respects this kind of
movement between incompatible conceptual orders has to do with the relation between a
dream as a whole and our waking life. Dreams are capable of including everything that
exists or occurs in waking life, in such a way that no part of a dream need establish that it
is different from waking life. This is why the skeptical problem of knowing whether we
are dreaming or awake is so hard and perhaps impossible to answer. Nonetheless, the
elements of the content of dreams are not the same things as their equivalents in waking
life. Since the elements of dreams can all be indistinguishable from those of waking life,
dreams and waking life can therefore in the end only be distinguished each as a whole, or
with respect to their framing of the sense of the whole of things. In Fechner’s words, a
dream is an altogether “different scene” from waking life (Freud, 1976 [1900], p. 112): it
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
4
doesn’t fit into or directly belong in our waking world, even when its own internal
content is entirely consistent with that world. As a result, the process of recollecting and
working with dreamsin other words, the process by which dreams have meaning for
usitself involves a movement or comparison between mutually exclusive conceptual
orders, and often between conceptual orders that each re-situate in their own context the
“same” things, events, and concerns as the other.
I shall give further support for this view of dreams in the course of trying to
justify my suggestion that it helps to account for the various aspects of dreams I outlined
above. In addition, that it does help to account for these various dimensions of dreams is
itself, in turn, another kind of support for this view.
If dreams are partly this kind of movement or comparison between different
conceptual orders, they consist partly in our awareness of what makes these conceptual
orders and overall frameworks different. As a result, they consist partly in an awareness
of these orders’ or frameworks’ structuring categories or concepts themselves, which are
the source of the difference. This is what I mean by dreams as a meta-conceptual
experience.
If this kind of awareness of overall conceptual orders is possible, we can also
achieve it more directly, by simply reflecting on our view of things as a whole and so on
its structuring concepts. These two forms of this awareness are two sides of the same
coin. On the one hand, as I have noted, the comparison between different frameworks
necessarily involves awareness of the frameworks themselves. On the other hand,
awareness of our framework as a whole necessarily means that we are no longer situated
within it, that we are no longer governed by its structuring concepts and categories. As a
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
5
result, we are moving between or comparing a conceptual order and an order
incompatible with it. When dreams involve this kind of awareness, then, they involve
both kinds of experience: movement or comparison between frameworks and reflection
on our own framework as a whole. A particular dream may be concerned more
specifically with one rather than the other, or may be concerned with both of them
equally.
The categories or concepts in terms of which we understand the world, however,
cannot simply be separated from the world and set over against it as an object of
awareness on their own. There is no world for us without the concepts that organize it
into meaning for us, and there are no concepts without the features and details of a world
that make up their content.
3
Consequently, our most basic or world-structuring concepts
are part of the substance of our world. In fact, since they structure the world, they are
what we might call an anatomy of the world. This is the thesis, for example, of Kant’s
Critique of Pure Reason (1929 [1781/1787]), and is also part of the point of
Wittgenstein’s (e.g., 1958) idea of the “grammars” of concepts as, to put it crudely, the
structures of our concrete activities in the world and of the content of what those
activities make of the world. Consequently, Wittgenstein argues that “the truth of certain
empirical propositions belongs to our frame of reference” (1969, p. 12e): the conceptual
3
Kant (1929 [1781/1787]) famously argued that “Thoughts without content are empty,
intuitions without concepts are blind. It is, therefore, just as necessary to make our
concepts sensible, that is, to add the object to them in intuition, as to make our intuitions
intelligible, that is, to bring them under concepts” (A51, B75). See also, for example,
Winch (1958) for a Wittgensteinian discussion of the same point.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
6
frame in whose terms we interpret the world is partly given as the direct, empirical truth
of the world itself. To say that dreams are a meta-conceptual experience, then, is also to
say that they are an experience of the anatomy, fabric, or structure of our experience itself
and therefore of what we experience as and mean by the world or reality itself. This is not
just subjective: it is the structure of everything we mean and so everything we refer to by
our concepts “reality” or “world.” Dreams are an existential or metaphysical experience,
an experience or awareness of the nature of existence itself.
There are a number of dream theorists who also think of dreams as at least in
some respects a reflection on the nature or structure of our lives as a whole and even of
reality as a whole. Jung (1974 [1934]), for example, sees the analysis of dreams as a
process that “finally reaches completion in the restoration of the total personality” (p.
108). States (1993) argues that dreams allow us to see how the meanings of our world
blend, so that in contrast with grasping “local meaning” we experience “the condition of
meaningfulness that pervades experience in the form of a felt unity” (p. 192).
4
As a result,
in dreaming “one is always in a state at least slightly outside the world” (p. 191). And
elsewhere he writes, ‘my dream . . . is the pulse and direction of my existence. . . . the
dreamer cannot detect the beginning of his dream because for that interval the dream is
all of his consciousness that exists. The dream is the center and the horizon of his world’
(States, 1988, p. 85). Valberg (2007) in fact focuses on the all-embracing “horizon” of
dreams to help establish the necessity in waking thought of the idea of a view of the
world or of one’s life as a whole (e.g., pp. 69-70). Binswanger (1963 [1930]) insists that
4
States argues here that this is an experience of felt unity that concepts do not do justice
to, but I am proposing that concepts are really part of feelings and vice versa.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
7
“the dream . . . is nothing other than a particular mode of human existence in general” (p.
227), and that “our whole existence moves within the meaning matrix” of the dream (p.
223). Finally, Boss (1957 [1953]) argues that a person’s dreams involve “relationships
with things and with people” that “go to make up his entire existence” (p. 122), and that
express “the total and original essence of things as such” (p. 101).
There is a contradiction in the idea of our becoming aware of our interpretation of
reality in general and as a whole. If what we are talking about is truly our interpretation
of reality as a whole, our framework for the meaning or sense of everything, then we
cannot step outside it to gain a vantage point that allows us to register it as a whole and
still be capable of making sense. And yet, as we grow as human beings, we do move from
one overall view of things to another; and we do learn to understand views that are
globally different from our own and unintelligible in the terms of our own, and
consequently to recognize what characterizes our own framework as a contrasting whole.
Let me suggest baldly, then, that the deeper dimensions of human insight do therefore
work in a way that is partly contradictory.
As I have discussed elsewhere, however, it is no longer uncontroversially the case
that contradiction is always unacceptable (e.g., Barris, 2010, 2014).
5
And it is a recurrent
theme of philosophical thought that a full account of things requires us to account for
sense itself: in other words, that making sense itself requires us to reflect on sense and so
5
On the admissibility of contradictions in formal logic see, for example, Priest, 2001;
Bremer, 2005, esp. pp. 16, 19ff. For discussion on both sides of this debate, see Priest,
Beall, and Armour-Garb, 2004. For the acceptability of contradiction in informal
contexts, see, for instance, Johnstone, 1978, p. 45.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
8
to a greater or lesser extent to remove ourselves from it or at least from taking it for
granted (in addition to the long tradition of metaphysics both west and east, see, for
example, Derrida, 1981 [1972], p. 6; Jaspers, 1997 [1935], p. 111; Wittgenstein, 1961
[1921]; and, on the need to account for the whole, if not to step outside sense, Nagel,
1979). There are, again, well-known objections to the legitimate sense of the idea of a
“whole” of our sense-making that we can get a grasp of (e.g., Davidson, 1984; Rorty,
1991), but, like the comprehensive rejection of contradiction, these objections are not
uncontroversial (see, for instance, MacIntyre, 1988, p. 374; Putnam, 1990, p. 104).
The particular contradiction I am proposing is limited in its consequences. It does
not affect the sense of the world as we experience it when we are not reflecting on it as a
whole, but only arises in the limited context of this particular kind of experience. And it
is manageable: once we are caught up in the contradiction, it resolves itself. The idea of
being outside all sense includes the sense of this idea itself: as we think it through, it
cancels its own meaning. Consequently it returns us to familiar sense (to the “inside” of
our framework), to a position of being able to start again from the beginning in thinking
about the issues of sense.
6
Like our basic sense-making categories, this contradiction that sense requires is
not just a conceptual structure simply separated from the world. As a structure of sense, it
is also a structure of the reality of which this is the sense. Reality itself, I am proposing,
includes moments or elements of (self-resolving) incoherence.
7
Encountering and
6
On the logic of this process, see, for example, Barris, 2003, 2012, 2014.
7
As Dewey, for example, argues, “indeterminate situations . . . are disturbed, troubled,
ambiguous, confused, full of conflicting tendencies, obscure, etc. It is the situation that
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
9
undergoing this contradiction is therefore also both a meta-conceptual and an existential
or metaphysical experience.
As I shall argue, this limited and manageable contradiction helps us to make sense
not only of the recurrent themes of human experience and thought I have mentioned but
also of a variety of puzzling aspects of dreams. It therefore seems that there is good
reason at least to explore ways of working with this contradiction and see where they take
us. Part of what I shall be trying to do in this essay is to identify and map out some of the
details of how this contradiction operates and of how it may manageably be worked with.
2. The Peculiar Logical Relations and Transitions in Dreams
Insofar as dreams consist in a movement or comparison between two comprehensively
different sense frameworks, or between a framework and its “outside,” where the
framework’s sense-making categories comprehensively no longer operate in the same
way, they consist in a transition from one kind of sense or logic to another, incompatible
kind. One and the same experience or thing is now construed according to an
incompatible logic, and therefore means something incompatibly different. In other
words, in terms of the possibilities for sense in either framework or context, this
has these traits. We are doubtful because the situation is inherently doubtful. . . . The
notion that in actual existence everything is completely determinate has been rendered
questionable by the progress of physical science itself. Even if it had not been, complete
determination would not hold of existences as an environment. For nature is an
environment only as it is involved in interaction with an organism, or self” (1938, pp.
105-6).
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
10
transition or comparison consists in a logical error of some kind: a contradiction, a non
sequitur, or a conceptual confusion. Since, however, each framework is global and so, in
its terms, exhaustive of all possible sense, there are no relevant alternative possibilities
for sense. As a result, the logical error is an objective and necessary part of the sense of
the situation.
8
It might naturally be objected that if the frameworks are truly globally different,
then it is not a case of one and the same thing becoming incompatibly different, but that,
instead, we are simply not discussing the same thing at all. As a result, there is no logical
error or confusion: it is not the case that one thing means incompatible things, or is being
understood in incompatible ways. But this is exactly the point. It is true that it is not the
same thing at all. And yet, in the case of movement or comparison between frameworks,
it is also true that we have moved into understanding the new framework on the basis of
beginning with the old one or, in the case of comparison, on the basis of the context of
the old onesince the frameworks are global, there is no other basis on which to have
begun and no other context in which to begin to construe. Consequently what we meant
by the one experience or thing in the first framework has itself transformed into or
become taken as the incompatibly meant experience or thing. It both is the same thing
and yet is not in any way the same thing.
9
Correspondingly, in the case of perspective on
8
In Barris (2010), I argue more fully on this basis that these kinds of violations of logic in
dreams are sometimes legitimate. In this section of this essay, I explore in more detail the
nature and variety of these legitimate logical anomalies we find in dreams.
9
On the sameness of the thing construed in these incompatible ways (although without
thinking of it as involving the logical paradox that I argue it does), see also, for example,
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
11
one’s own framework as a whole, the sense of the framework has itself required
movement beyond the purchase of that same sense. In other words, the principles of sense
that established the framework’s contents as meaning what they do have themselves
produced the movement beyond themselves. As a result, the principles that make each
thing what it is no longer apply in consequence of their own application: that is, they both
apply and do not apply. (Alternatively expressed, the new sense is a result of the self-
transformation of the old sense: the new thing is in some sense continuous withthough
nonetheless also wholly incompatible withthe old thing.) Consequently, one and the
same thing that made sense no longer does. This is a consequence of exactly the
particular contradiction that, I have argued, sense itself requires us to accept and explore
in this kind of context.
Since in this kind of context logical errors are part of sense itself, then, insofar as
dreams involve this transition between different logical orders the peculiarly illogical
relations and transitions that we find in them make sense, or at least they make what we
might call a logically legitimate inadequacy of sense. Dreams typically involve and are
often largely structured by non sequiturs of statement, inference, and setting; by
contradictions as, for example, one thing becomes another, incongruously different one;
and by conceptual confusions as one category of thing seems naturally to operate as
another (say, one’s own sensation of a sweet taste can be directly inspected and explored
MacIntyre (1989): “each community, using its own criteria of sameness and difference,
recognizes that it is one and the same subject matter about which they are advancing their
claim; incommensurability and incompatibility are not incompatible” (p. 190). For further
discussion of this issue, see Barris, 2014, e.g., chapter 3, section 6.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
12
by others, as though it were a publicly accessible object). If a dream consists in an overall
movement or comparison between incompatible logical orders, it makes sense that many
of the events within it would consist in immediate relations or transitions between
logically incompatible elements like these.
It also makes sense that the specific character of the overall transition or
comparison in which the dream as a whole partly consists would govern part of the nature
and sequence of the particular transitions or relations within it. (Similarly, the specifics of
the overall transition or reflection in which a series of dreams participates and partly
consists would account for part of the nature and sequence of the experiences from dream
to dream.) So, for example, in the case of a movement between frameworks, it would
make sense that one phase of the movement involves a process well expressed by
journeying, and doing so through, say, a desert without a visible sun in the sky, because
in this kind of transition there are no orientation clues or “landmarks” to tell what the
appropriate direction of travel is. We are between frameworks, and so without a
consistent criterion for how to proceed in making sense of our situation. But once a new
framework has crystallized for us, there are then consistent ways of orienting ourselves,
of making sense of the issues. What is more, there is only one ultimate way of doing so:
when we are simply within a framework, the “outside” of sense simply has no sense or
meaning at all; that idea itself is outside the conditions that structure sense. This situation
would then be well expressed by images and concepts to which both journeying and
fundamental disorientation are entirely irrelevant: say, an image of stirring one’s tea at
home and simply enjoying its swirl and color. A dream that expresses both these phases
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
13
of the transition would appropriately involve an abrupt shift of context from one set of
images and concepts to another, wholly incompatible set.
In between these two phases, while the new framework is still crystallizing but is
not yet established, is still fragmentary and uncertain, it would make sense that this
situation is well expressed by images and concepts that combine in themselves the
incompatible states of being inside and outside a framework of sense: say, feeling
relieved at having arrived and yet still being preoccupied with trying to find one’s way, or
simply being in a state of having arrived and yet not having arrived, all at once.
On this conception of dreams, then, because the overall movement by its nature
violates logic and conceptual integrity, the direction and sequence of the transitions and
relations must necessarily often be in some ways logically “wrong.” Belonging to neither
framework (or to both), they must violate the criteria for progress and appropriateness
that belong to both. It would make sense, therefore, if they consisted partly in going off at
tangents, or even in the opposite direction to the one that leads to their goal, or in going in
more than one direction at the same time, and if they sometimes carried out their goal by
performing activities completely unrelated to that goal. In other words, it would make
sense if genuine progress and appropriate connection themselves within dreams consisted
partly in non sequiturs, contradictions, and category confusions.
In this kind of context, for example, there are logical peculiarities in the nature of
sequence itself. For instance, in the case where we are moving between incompatible
comprehensive or global conceptual frameworks (again, this “movement” includes our
simply coming to understand a new framework in order to compare the two), we have to
enter the new framework of sense before we can begin to see the sense it makes. The only
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
14
way we can get to the new framework, however, is on the basis of the resources of sense
we already have in our current framework. We therefore need to begin by construing the
elements of our experience in a way that approximates those of the new framework. But
because our current framework and the new one are globally different, all the relevant
elements or materials for construal in each mean something different in the other, and in
fact exclude the meanings of the other. As a result, there is no common ground, no basis
in our current framework for entering that other kind of sense. We can therefore begin to
re-construe our current sense only by already being within that new framework. In other
words, in order to take the steps that will get us to the new framework, we have to be
there already. And yet, we do get into new frameworks of this kind: which means that
this oddity of sequence, or something like what it describes, must in fact take place. In
this context, then, orderly sequence itself becomes disordered.
We can see the same thing by considering the relations between global conceptual
(or sense) frameworks and particular meanings or concepts. If we are not attending
specifically to the meaning or concept of a thing, but only to the thing’s role in our
immediate concerns, we tend to see it only in the terms that most easily make sense, that
is, in the terms of our current framework. In that kind of contextsimply within a
frameworkparticular things and events are unequivocally what they are, and as a result
are also simply and straightforwardly situated in relation to each other in (among their
other relations) space and sequence. But if we attend to the meaning or sense or concept
of the thing or event, beyond its immediate place in our concerns, we can relevantly
recognize that there are conflicting possible general contexts that can frame its sense, and
that as a result the appropriate concept or sense of the thing is at some points undecided.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
15
These are the kind of “border territory” contexts that conceptual analysis often deals with.
(For example, in the early stages of a child’s learning language, there may be a phase
when we cannot decide definitively whether she is uttering words whose meaning she
grasps or whether she is still merely imitating sounds: our criteria for both may apply. Or,
more sharply, a physical entity may behave both definitively as a particle, having clear
boundaries, and also definitively as a wave or process, without clear boundaries: our
criteria for both of mutually exclusive properties may definitively apply to it.) As a result,
in this kind of context the thing is not unequivocally what it is, and so is not
unequivocally situated in its relations to others with respect (among other issues) to
where each is and to which thing or event depends on which, and in what way. In that
kind of context, therefore, the thing is not unequivocally situated in relation to others with
respect to spatial connection and sequence.
Now dreams, as I have suggested, do in fact register conceptual structures, and
therefore concepts or sense themselves, and not only the particulars that are constituted
and structured by that sense. And they do so in a context in which conflicting sense
frameworks are not only relevant but salient. As a result, it is natural for dreams, given
this kind of context, directly to register and portray the disordered sequence (or spatial
relations) occurring at the level of the concepts or meanings of things and events, and not
only the sequence as it appears in the context of the immediate, simply-within-a-
framework functioning of the things and events. For example, in this light it makes sense
for a dreamer both to experience an arrival as occurring before the departure that got the
dreamer there, and yet still also to understand and experience the arrival as dependent on
the departure and so as coming after it. This is not simply a mistake in logic and sense
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
16
(although it is that too). Instead, as I have argued, it is an expression of a logical error or
confusion required by sense itself in this kind of sense-conflicted context, and therefore
inherent in and part of the real situation.
Again, in general, the logical errors I have discussed in this section are not just a
matter of dreams’ being unreal and therefore exempt from the laws of logic. Because this
movement between incompatible orders of sense is real, it is a movement in which sense
itself genuinely changes. As a result, the logical errors that are part of this movement are
also part of reality, of sense as it is actually functioning in this situation. In other words,
these logical errors are logically legitimate or valid.
As I mentioned in the first section of this essay, this kind of movement,
comparison, or reflection between or on sense frameworks as a whole is also part of the
deep growth and perplexities that occur in our waking life. Or, rather, it is partly because
it occurs in our waking life that it also occurs in dreams. In these contexts, the odd logic
of dreams is therefore not really peculiar to them, but belongs equally to the deepest
dimensions of waking life. Rather than being peculiar to dreams, it is peculiar to depth of
meaning and sense. In this respect, dreams are not privileged as a source of insight.
In the next section, however, in discussing the feeling texture of dreams, I shall
argue that their expression and enactment of this transition or comparison between
overall frameworks of sense or of reflection on our overall framework is often more pure,
and so in a sense simpler, than the equivalent experiences in waking life. And in this
respect dreams are privileged as a source of insight. In addition, as I also suggest in the
next section, in dreaming we also often give ourselves over more unreservedly to our
experience than we do in waking life. For both of these reasons, the dream experience
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
17
shows its anatomy or logical structure with less clutter and so more clearly than the
waking life versions of the same deep experience do.
There is a different kind of paradox in the relation and movement between
incompatible conceptual orders that, although it does not necessarily involve meta-
conceptual awareness, is a consequence of the character of conceptual structures and has
many of the same effects on the logic of dreams (and also, in fact, of waking life) as the
ones I have been discussing. It therefore seems worth mentioning here. This paradox
results from the relation between the mutual exclusiveness of concepts and, in contrast
with the meta-conceptual case, the ways in which they are embedded in (as it were, the
face they turn to) the particularities of the world as it is within our sense framework and
within the relevant conceptual orders. Because concepts acquire and have their meaning
within complex forms of life (to use Wittgenstein’s term), these meanings are constituted
in interaction with those of very different concepts. In other words, they are internally
dependent on their relations with concepts whose content, considered on its own, is
external to theirs. For example, the concept of “emotional progress” or “emotional
health” has different content depending on whether the concept of “vulnerability” is
connected with or disconnected from the concepts of “weakness” and “failure” or,
alternatively, say, those of “strength” and “courage.”
As a result, in order to gain a new concept and then also to consolidate our
competence in working with it, we often need to spend time absorbed in the issues
connected with very different concepts, issues that are in themselves irrelevant to those
connected with the concept we are aiming towards and that may even involve movement
in opposite directions from those relevant to that concept. So, for instance, learning to
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
18
regard uncomfortable feelings of helplessness as unqualifiedly acceptable may be
necessary preparation for learning to feel at ease: it may be necessary so that, for
example, we can feel confident that we can handle feeling helpless should it happen, and
therefore need not keep ourselves rigid in order to ward it off or deny it. (This kind of
preparation may be necessary even if at some level we have already learned and come to
accept the relevant insights and so taken up their concomitant attitudes. We can be in
conflict with ourselves, even to the extent of grasping or accepting at one level what we
do not at another.)
Like the paradoxes arising from meta-conceptual awareness, I suggest, these
logically surprising relations between concepts are expressed in dreams, and account for
some of the odd relations and transitions in them. While this kind of paradox is important
and interesting in its own right, however, it expresses a different phenomenon from that
of meta-conceptual awareness. I mention it mainly because of the interesting overlap of
effects. It is also worth noting, however, that there may be more than one kind of reason
why some types of logical errors in dreams (and elsewhere) are, although genuine errors,
also logically legitimate. In this case, the logical paradox lies in the internal constitution
of concepts by other concepts that are nonetheless external to them. This paradox shares
with the meta-conceptual paradox the violation of boundaries of sense, but where the
meta-conceptual paradox consists in a direct interaction of the incompatible concepts
themselves, in this case the direct interaction and conflict is between the consequences,
for our particular issues and experiences, of separate and independent explorations of
each concept. In fact, the presence of a paradox only becomes evident if we trace the
source of the conflict to the mutual dependence of the incompatible concepts that makes
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
19
it necessary. As a result, its actual expression in experience and practice is not
immediately paradoxical, but on the face of it is just a conflict between different concepts
that are relevant at different times or in different respects.
3. The Feeling Texture of Dreams
There is a distinctive texture of feeling that is common in dreams. Within a dream, we
often experience our feelings as unqualified or pure. For example, we experience
unmitigated delight or unqualified horror, or a naked and vulnerable poignancy of
feeling, in which we are caught up without reserve for moments or for the entire dream.
Even when this intensely pure aspect of dream feeling is not part of our awareness of the
experience during the dream, it often becomes evident when we remember the dream
after waking because of the contrast of the dream experience with our typical waking
experience.
Another characteristic of the experience of dreams (related to the first
characteristic, as I shall argue below) is that they often feel uncanny: we are undergoing
the dream experience, and yet somehow it does not fit into what we can conceive. The
experience is made of elements that make sense to us, since we can react to and engage
with them. And yet these same elements seem deeply unfamiliar, do not seem part of the
world as we are accustomed to it. The same elements both fit and do not fit with our
familiar world. In addition, the way the elements connect with each other follows a logic
that does not make sense in our waking context, and yet seems unexceptionable in the
context of the dream. When we remember the dream after waking, this dimension of the
dream experience too makes sense and yet does not make sense. (Towards the end of this
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
20
section I discuss the possibility of registering our intact dream experience within the
context of our waking experiencedespite their consisting in wholly incompatible
frameworks of sense, as I argue they do.) This is the uncanny: not what is simply weird
or unintelligible, but what is simultaneously and in the same respects both weird and
familiar, intelligible while at the same time it cannot be.
I suggest that these two characteristics of dream feeling, its unreserved or
unqualified character and its uncanniness, are related in that they are opposite dimensions
or effects of the same thing. It will be easiest to show why this might be so by beginning
with the uncanny dimension of dream feeling, and showing how the meta-conceptual
character of dreams accounts for it.
I have suggested that dreams consist partly in a movement outside the framework
in whose terms we make sense of the world as a whole, of things in general. In fact, for
the same reasons, this can also be a movement outside a particular, more limited
conceptual order within the whole, a movement that reflects on that conceptual structure
itself, compares it another, or moves from it to another. The same considerations apply to
both cases, and so for convenience I shall take discussion of either to stand in for
discussion of the other as well.
I proposed, further, that this movement is either part of a comparison with or
transition to a different general outlook, or of a metaphysical or existential reflection on
one’s life as a whole or on reality as a whole (or on a particular structure within these,
itself as a whole). In either case, however, in reflecting on our sense-making framework
as a whole, the dream consists partly in stepping outside of that framework. But if it were
simply a step into nothing, we would not have the resource of any categories for making
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
21
sense, and would have no meaningful experience at all. (Or, in the case of particular
structures, we would have no experience that is relevantly meaningful.) Instead, it is a
stepping to the specific outside of that particular framework: we are aware of the
categories in which the world makes sense to us, but that awareness involves a distance
from them and so is no longer simply structured and guided by them. We have, as it were,
one foot inside the framework and one foot out.
This directly describes the experience of the uncanny. The world makes the same
sense it always did; all the same elements of sense are exactly as they have always and
familiarly been; and yet it is not the same sense, we have an unfamiliar orientation
towards all of it. And because it is our sense of things in general and as a whole (or, in the
case of particular structures, our sense of relevant things as a whole) that we have
distanced ourselves from, there is no simply familiar ground, left out of this distancing
from familiar sense, on which to stand and get a clear perspective on the experience and
so separate what makes familiar sense from what does not. As a result, everything
indistinguishably both fits and does not fit with familiar sense: in other words, everything
fits and does not fit familiar sense all at once and in the same, or indistinguishable,
respects.
Where the movement in which the dream consists involves a comparison between
more than one general outlook, we also have our “outside” foot inside a specific different
framework, with different, incompatible categories for the sense of things. Here, in
addition to being both within and outside sense simultaneously, we also have a conflict
and confusion between incompatible ways of making definite sense of the same things.
As I discussed in the previous section of the paper, this is part of what accounts for the
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
22
peculiar logical relations and transitions in dreams. Here, though, it gives a second part of
the explanation of the uncanny feeling texture of dreams. The elements of the experience,
in this way too, make familiar sense but at the same time and in the same respects do not.
I suggested above that this same meta-conceptual character of dreams also
accounts for the unreserved nature of dream feeling. More specifically, I suggested that
this characteristic of dream feeling is the opposite effect of the same basic meta-
conceptual structure. In discussing the uncanny aspect of dream feeling, I drew on the
idea that this perspective on or experience outside of the sense of the whole of things is in
contradictory conflict with itself with respect to its own sense. Another aspect of this
perspective or experience, however, is that its content is detached from any of the
particular issues within the whole, and so from all the conflicting and mutually qualifying
variety of considerations that they involve. As Ortega y Gasset (1960 [1929]) argues, “the
Universe, or all there is, is not each one of the things there are, but only the universal
aspect of each thing, therefore only a facet of each thing. In this sense, but only this, the
object of philosophy [that is, all there is or the whole of things] also is partial, in that it is
the part through which each thing is inserted into the whole” (p. 105, my insertion). The
perspective or reflection in which dream experience partly consists is, then, essentially
one-sided in a way that regular within-the-whole experience is not. It is not subject to all
the variety of possible relevant partial perspectives that the surrounding detail of
additional contexts brings.
10
(Similarly, reflection on a particular, more limited
10
This theoretically motivated suggestion fits nicely with Rechtschaffen’s empirically
based observation that the manifest content of dreams is characteristically “single-
minded” or “isolated” in the sense of showing a “strong tendency for a single train of
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
23
conceptual order or structure as a whole within the larger whole is essentially one-sided
in a way that reflection on the detailed content within that particular structure is not. So,
for example, reflection on the concept of color in general is indifferent to many of the
considerations involved in reflecting on redness, on greenness, on the contrasts and
complementarities between the two, and so on.)
Further, although the dream is an awareness of the sense of the whole of things
(or of a whole if more limited conceptual structure), it is typically this whole conceived
and therefore experienced only in terms of its relation to and bearing on one or a few
particular issues within it. We exist as parts within the whole, and so we initially
conceptualize the whole in terms of issues that arise in connection with our experiences
among and with its particulars. And, for the same reason, we also think of the difference
the achieved conception of the whole makes in terms of its meaning for particular issues
within the whole. In addition, since the dream is nonetheless a perspective on the whole
and not on the details within the whole, it separates, as I have noted, the particular issues
in whose terms this overall perspective is conceived from all the alternative kinds of
considerations that reflection on within-the-whole issues, being embedded in and
connected with a wider context, might bring.
In other words, then, dream experience is structurally simpler than any of our
experiences within the whole.
11
It is therefore essentially more capable of being wholly
related thoughts and images to persist over extended periods without disruption or
competition from other simultaneous thoughts and images” (1978, p. 97).
11
Boss also argues for the structural simplicity of dreams, but gives an account of it that
is the reverse of my own. Where I try to account for the intensity of feeling in dreams on
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
24
and unequivocally absorbing than those within-the-whole experiences, which are more
typical of waking life.
Even more than this, however, as I mentioned above in discussing the uncanny
dimension of dream feeling, because dream experience is partly of the whole of sense or
the whole of things, there is no contrasting ground on which to stand and get a
perspective on this experience in turn. During the course of the experience, it is the only
conceivable experience and set of feelings. In this more radical respect too, then, the
meta-conceptual character of dreams explains why feelings in dreams can be absorbing in
a peculiarly unqualified and unreserved way.
the basis of dreams’ simplicity, he accounts for dreams’ simplicity on the basis of the
simplicity and intensity of feeling. He notes that “dreamers so frequently perceive only a
single person or very few people and only a very limited number of objects,” and
suggests that this is because “the dreamer . . . is frequently, and intensely in a very
definite mood. Corresponding to this unequivocal mood, only those objects and people
are allowed to enter the respective dream world whose essence and being correspond
exactly to the behaviour patterns in which the dreamer himself happens to be moving. . . .
Corresponding to his concentrated mood the dreamer can enter into these realms of
existence and behaviour all the more vividly. It is for this reason that he feels closer to
their things and people, and that they can all be united in a single dream world of the
moment, however far removed in time and space they may be in his waking life” (pp.
111-12). I do argue in the next section, however, that feelings are the privileged avenue
for interpreting dreams.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
25
It is true that some contrast is necessary for an experience to occur at all. But as I
have suggested, “stepping outside” a whole sense framework really means having, as it
were, one foot in and one foot outside the framework. As a result, in this contradictory
situation of being “outside the whole,” there is both no contrast, since it is the exhaustive
whole and nothing is left over to contrast the experience of it with, and yet there also is a
contrast with either the “inside” (despite the fact this is also, nonetheless, where we
already are) or with another global framework of the sense of things (despite the fact that
each framework is completely and so exclusively exhaustive of the whole). Again, as I
pointed out in the first section above, it is sense itself that requires us to reflect on and so
partially to distance ourselves from sense itself in general and as a whole, and as a result
to come upon and work with this kind of contradiction. The contradiction is part of the
working of sense itself in this kind of context.
I argued at the end of the first section that this contradictory idea of being outside
all sense cancels its own sense and consequently returns us to familiar sense, “within” our
framework. In this connection, another way of expressing this simultaneity of no contrast
and yet contrast in reflection on the whole of things is that, in the context of that
reflection, we are, as it were, wholly “inside” the “outside” itself, and so have no
perspective on it; as a result, it is not yet truly a perspective on the whole of things. That
is, on its own, this reflection does not yet fully make its own sense. It is only the
comprehensive reflection which it is, that is, it is only completely itself, when it has also
“stepped outside” itself and so returned us to the unreflective “inside” of our framework
(which is all that is left out of that reflection on the whole and so is its own “outside”). Its
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
26
contradictory cancellation of itself, then, is not just a negation of it but is genuinely part
of it, of what it successfully is.
12
This contradictory simultaneity of global and therefore mutually exclusive
frameworks also explains why, in remembering the dream after waking, we can register
the wholly “other” nature of the experience of the dream, its nature as wholly excluding
our waking sense and region of things (and vice versa), while nonetheless also being able
to experience it in contrast with and so in the context of our waking sense of things.
There is another element of this movement partly outside the constraints of sense
as a whole that helps to account for the often unreserved absorption in dream feelings.
This movement partly outside familiar sense means that not grasping the sense of the
experience, not understanding, is an inherent part of the dream experience. This gives a
further explanation for the lack of tempering perspective and so for the open vulnerability
to impressions and the untempered absorption in feelings we often experience in dreams.
Again, as I pointed out in the first section of this essay, this kind of reflection on
or movement or comparison between different senses of the whole of things is also part
of the deep growth and perplexities that occur in our waking life. Both this kind of
waking experience and this kind of dream experience deal with the whole of things (or
the whole of a particular conceptual order or structure), and so are detached from the
complicating variety of particulars “within” our framework and the multitude of
12
Ortega’s description above of the whole of things that is the object of philosophy as
itself partial is therefore true but, because the sense of or what we mean by this object is
self-canceling in this way, incomplete. Perhaps this is the burden of his qualification that
the whole of things is partial “in this sense, but only this.”
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
27
considerations and perspectives they bring to bear. We might ask, then, how this view of
dreams accounts for the difference in the feeling texture of the waking and dreaming
versions of this kind of experience.
I do think there is some overlap: the waking experiences are in some ways
overwhelming and in those respects absorb us wholly in them, without perspective. It is
also hard to be clear about their validity or reality. But there are also differences in the
two versions of the experience. I suggest that in waking life, when we are caught up in
the view of the whole, we are nonetheless at the same time substantially aware of the
multitude of everyday issues within our lives and world, even if our attention is not or is
only vaguely on them. In dreams, by contrast, we are more wholly and unreservedly
caught up in the experience of the whole, and much more or entirely oblivious to the
competing details of the experience simply “from within” our framework.
13
As a result,
the dream experience is a more pure version of that experience of the whole. And,
further, because of that purity, as I have argued, we also give ourselves over more
unreservedly to the experience than we do in waking life.
4. Some Dimensions of the Grounds and Nature of Dream Interpretation
I have suggested that dreams are partly an expression and undertaking of a movement
beyond our structuring categories of sense. This is a movement that necessarily also
begins in and is based on those structuring categories, since they structure all the sense
that exists for us, including the sense of all movement and change. These categories are
13
Compare again Rechtschaffen’s (1978) discussion of the “single-mindedness” of
dreams.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
28
consequently the basis and means of moving beyond themselves. As a result, dreams are
partly a movement and process of those foundational categories. That is, the experience
in which dreams consist, in all its intimate subjectivity, is not just a reflection on our
fundamental structure of meanings, but partly is that structure itself in process. The
dream experience is we ourselves, or, more precisely, the essentials or anatomy of us
ourselvesthe basic truth of usin process. It is an activity of our being.
Now, our subjective experience of our dreams upon waking, as the experience we
remember and recount, and our further honest subjective reactions (such as associations)
to them are also more or less essential parts of our make-up or substance, of who we are.
And in this context they are responses to and therefore directly connected with the
activity of our being in which our dreams partly consist. They are therefore expressions
and developments of that same activity of our being. As a result, these subjective
reactions are objective guides to the meaning of our dreams. What is more, because
dreams are not merely a reflective awareness but a process of our being, our subjective
reactions to them are indispensable or necessary as objective guides to their meaning.
Since their meaning partly consists in an activity of our being, we miss that meaning if
we replace it with the kind of reflective observation that is not part of that particular
activity. (This is not to say that our subjective reactions are the only important guide to
the dream’s meaning. I shall return to this below.)
I have also argued that the conceptual structure that dreams in some respects
express and enact is not just the structure of our personal being but also of what we mean
by being or reality in general. Here I want to emphasize only that the categories our
dreams express are not just the basics of our subjective views, wishes, and fantasies about
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
29
ourselves, but the foundations of our own true being itself. These categories are the
foundations of, so to speak, the objective reality of our subjectivity. In this connection,
Boss’s (1957 [1953]) phenomenological understanding of dreams also sees our
subjectivity as, further, fully a dimension of reality in general. In that framework, what
we artificially separate as subjective awareness and objective reality are in fact just
different dimensions or poles of the same thing and of each other. Consequently, the
structures of experience and awareness, including our awareness in dreams, are also the
structures of reality in general. As a result, dream interpretation can lead to “a new and
true relationship with the essence of all things” (p. 121).
It is true that, as an awareness, our experience is partly a simply descriptive
reflection to which participating in process and transformation are irrelevant. But in the
case of an awareness that moves beyond our fundamental sense-making categories, the
sense of these descriptions itself is shifting, so that in this context simple descriptive
statements are themselves already participating in a process of transformation or
qualification. On the other hand, this does not mean that their simply descriptive
character is entirely eliminated. As I have discussed, this movement beyond sense occurs
as a movement outside or a distancing ourselves from a specific framework of simply and
stably given sense, and it is therefore based and depends on that stably given sense. We
need, then, to respect both sides of the character of our descriptive awareness: detached
description or reflection, but at the same time a transformative process of the content of
this description.
The structure and resolution of this paradox are the same as those of the
contradiction of becoming aware of our framework as a whole that I discussed in the first
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
30
and third sections. A movement beyond our sense-categories in general is also a
movement beyond the sense of the categories of movement and transformation
themselves, and therefore reaches the point of not excluding what they exclude. As a
result, it comes to cancel their meaning as movement and transformation. In the end, the
very fact that our meanings are shifting turns back on its own meaning and restores our
meanings as stable, unchanging descriptions. But this only occurs fully once we are in the
new framework or restored to the no longer globally reflective “inside” of our original
framework, so that our foundational categories are no longer an issue for the questions
we are asking and so are left unqualified. Until then, both sides of the dream experience
and of our later reactions to the dreamtheir character as both simple descriptive
meaning and as transformation of meaning and so of beingoccur and need to be
respected.
To return, then, to my main theme: I have argued, on the basis of the meta-
conceptual nature of dreams, that the interpretation of dreams needs to be rooted in and
guided by the dreamer’s own honest expressions of and reactions to that experience. It
follows that the necessary core method of dream interpretation is the tradition that Freud
began (at least in the contemporary Western history of dream interpretation) of
privileging the dreamer’s narrative and choice of expressions in describing the dream,
and also her spontaneous associations with its elements.
Since the dream is a process of the dreamer’s being in general, its structure is the
structure of all of the dreamer’s experience during the dream, including her most
immediate experience within it. I suggest that the most immediate aspect of the dream
experience for the dreamer, the aspect of the experience that is most direct and in the
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
31
forefront of her awareness, is the feeling texture of the dream. If this is so, then the
feeling texture is, as it were, the leading edge of the process in the person of whose being
the dream is an activity. Or, approaching this same issue in a different way, because this
is a process of the sense of ourselves and our world and so (at some level) also of our
awareness, and in particular is partly the transforming awareness of our foundational
categories of sense, we might say that the feeling texture of the dream is the direct sense
(in the sense of “sensation”) of the structure of sense (in the sense of “meaning”) itself.
The feeling texture is therefore the most direct access to the meaning the dream has for
the dreamer: to its meaning both as activity of transformation and as the simply
descriptive content and reflections in which this activity, as an activity of awareness, also
consists. The feeling texture, then, is the most basic and so the most important access to
the dream’s interpretation.
That feelings are the primary avenue for interpreting dreams is given some
support by Boss’ argument, noted above, that “the dreamer . . . is frequently, and
intensely in a very definite mood. Corresponding to this unequivocal mood, only those
objects and people are allowed to enter the respective dream world whose essence and
being correspond exactly to the behaviour patterns in which the dreamer himself happens
to be moving” (1957 [1953], p. 112). States, on the basis of exploring how we might
construct our dreams, comes to the similar conclusion that “like the poets we dream about
things whose meaning we already know in an emotional and preconceptual sense, and
that is no doubt why we dream about them and why dreams make a certain kind of
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
32
essentialized sense. The dream is the instantiation of a felt meaning” (1993, p. 169).
14
This privileging of feeling texture also fits well with Gendlin’s (1986) emphasis on
feeling in his “focusing” approach to interpreting dreams, although he sees bodily feeling
in particular as most important. As will become clearer shortly below, his view fits with
my own as well in that, as he insists, the relevant feeling is not one that we can initially
identify: we “cannot say what it is” (p. 5). It is a feeling whose nature or sense we need to
establish.
The dreamer can helpfully engage the feeling texture of the dream in two ways.
First, she can dwell with it, allow it to “be there” without interference, without trying to
make anything of it one way or another. In this way the process of which it is the
immediate expression can carry out its transformative and insight-granting work. The
dream is a process of and beyond our structuring categories of sense, and actively trying
to make sense of it would necessarily impose the un-transforming constraints of our
current sense framework on it. That is, actively trying to make sense of it would miss
what is essential to the dream. On the positive side, making attentive and non-interfering
room for the feeling texture allows us to register and adjust to whatever shifts occur in the
process that it expresses, including the possible emergence of simply descriptive insights.
Second, the dreamer can give the feeling texture priority as the locus or topic of
reactions and associations. The dreamer helpfully engages these reactions and
associations in turn, too, partly by dwelling with them, letting them work within her as
14
As I noted above, while States argues here that this is a felt, preconceptual meaning that
concepts do not do justice to, I am proposing that concepts are really part of feelings and
vice versa.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
33
the sense-emerging process that they are. These reactions, however, are less immediately
expressions of the dream process, and therefore do not all consist most directly in a
feeling texture. As a result, there are other dimensions of them, such as purely descriptive
elements, that become more prominent than they are in the feeling texture, and are
appropriately worked with in other ways.
There are, of course, dimensions of the dream experience itself that are not its
feeling texture, and that therefore need to be worked with in other ways. But I am
proposing that the feeling texture is the most basic and direct access to the dream’s
meaning and work.
With respect to interpretation of the dream, it is beside the point whether or not
the dreamer remembers the dream feeling as it was independently of his current waking
state of mind, or whether or not his reactions and associations capture the experience of
the dream as it was independently of its current narrative and interpretation. Since the
dream is the person’s own essential conceptual or existential experience, the same
process that is the meaning of the dream is also at work in the person’s later attentive
experience of and honest reactions to it.
I argued near the end of the previous section that we can make sense of
registering the wholly “other” nature of the dream experience even in the context of our
waking awareness. I am not retracting this here. The “otherness” remains wholly “other”
to our waking experience in the way I have discussed whether it is registered in the
context of our waking awareness and narrative or registered entirely within the dream. I
am only adding that it is the same “otherness” that we are dealing with in either case.
Another aspect of my account here that may also be puzzling is that this complete
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
34
otherness is what I have been arguing is an experience and activity of the person’s own
being. But I have argued this on the grounds that the experience and direct engagement of
our being involves “stepping outside” our sense framework and so outside our habitual
modes of making sense. As a result, whether in waking life or in dreaming, it is an
experience of occupying a conceptual order that is incompatible with sense as it is for us
within our framework and so in our typical experience.
The outside interpreter (that is, not the person who had the dream), too, can
helpfully engage the feeling texture by giving it priority as the locus of the dreamer’s
reactions and associations. I insisted above that the dreamer’s subjective reactions are
indispensable guides to the dream’s meaning. The outside interpreter, however, is also
extremely important in interpretation of the dream, exactly because she is not caught up
in the dream’s process. The dreamer’s experience is characterized precisely by being
caught up in a movement beyond her conceptual resources, and by being unusually
absorbed in that conceptually disorganized movement. For both reasons, it is very hard
for her to get an unconfused grasp of the concepts at issue and their relations to each
other. (I should note that “unconfused” here may include appropriate confusion in
accurately grasping legitimate logical incoherencies.) The capacity for a clear overview is
exactly what the dream is working towards her attaining once the work of the dream is
done. An outside interpreter, on the other hand, is less caught up both in some aspects of
the dreamer’s habitual, unreflective framework and in the conceptual disarray in which
the dream experience consists. She is therefore in a better position to register and adjust
to the complications or transformations of sense that the dreamer’s account and reactions
communicate.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
35
Whether it is the dreamer or an outside interpreter who is doing the interpreting,
however, it follows that he needs to allow himself to be guided not by his already-given
ways of making sense, but instead by the unexpected complications in sense that the
dream account offers. The kind of attitude that allows this is, I suggest, what Freud
described as “evenly-hovering attention,” in which the interpreter makes “no effort to
concentrate the attention on anything in particular” (1963 [1912], p. 118). Further,
because the dream consists precisely in working towards an overall sense of things (or a
relation between more than one overall sense of things) that has not yet emerged, it is
also important, as Freud insisted, not to begin with an impression of the overall dream,
but first to work with the dreamer’s reactions and associations to isolated elements of the
dream (e.g., 1976 [1900], p. 673), and on their basis to build towards a sense of the whole
or coordination of wholes. Here too, I suggest, and for the same reasons, the way to let
the unexpected whole emerge is by approaching the collection of these elements with the
attitude of ‘evenly hovering attention’ or, in other words, by dwelling with them in the
way I proposed above in connection with engaging the dream’s feeling texture.
I mentioned in the discussion of feeling texture that, because of the movement
beyond the constraints of sense, not understanding is an inherent part of the dream
experience. This is another way of talking about the incomplete or confused sense of the
dream process, and about the need for the interpreter to focus on and respect what she
does not understand in the dream account and not only what she does. Reik (1948), for
example, has emphasized this dimension of interpretation in the context of
psychoanalytic therapy. In a chapter titled “The courage not to understand,” he points out
that an explanation that is “plausible, rational, and comprehensible” often appears so
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
36
because of our habitual patterns of thoughtincluding those developed by training in
schools of interpretationrather than because of what the phenomenon, honestly
considered, offers (p. 509). Instead, he writes, we should learn “to postpone judgment and
put up with doubt” (p. 507).
As I discussed in the first section of this essay, a dream is (partly) a transition
between or beyond sense frameworks not only in itself, but also in the relation between
the dream as a whole and waking life. The contrast between the feeling texture of the
dream and the feeling texture or tone of our experience on waking from the dream is
therefore also part of the movement or reflection in which the dream consists and so of
the dream’s meaning. So, for example, on waking, a bad dream experience can feel less
bad or even good in contrast with or in the context of the waking feelings. One can feel,
for instance, relieved that it was just a dream, or pleased to have confronted a fear. And
pleasant feelings within a dream can feel bad in the light of the waking feelings. One
might, for instance, feel ashamed of having enjoyed behaving unfairly in the dream.
Since this contrast occurs after the dream experience, as its own independent
event, has ended, it is not part of the transition or reflection in which the dream’s own
content consists. But, as I have argued, part of what belongs to being a dream is that it is
a comprehensive shift of sense-framework from that of waking life. In other words, its
difference from waking life is part of what makes it internally what it is. In addition,
since for the person waking from the dream the contrast with waking life is a transition
between wholly different sense frameworks, that contrast is, equally with the dream, an
existential experience and process for him, and, what is more, one that is brought about
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
37
partly and substantially by the dream. These features of the dream’s contrast with waking
life therefore situate the dream and its internal content as part of a more general process.
I have discussed the logically legitimate confusions of sense and logic that occur
when incompatible sense frameworks are simultaneously relevant. Here I am suggesting
another of these paradoxes: that what is wholly and exclusively outside the dream, in the
comprehensively different sense framework of waking life, can be part of the sense of
what is wholly and exclusively inside the dream. (In the examples I gave, the contrast
with waking feelings changed the meaning of the feelings that occurred during the
dream.) Given the legitimate simultaneity of contradictory frameworks in this context, we
might even want to say that the contrast between dream and waking worlds both is
already part of the internal process of the dream itself and is simply, entirely, and
permanently outside it, or that it is both a result of the process the dream expresses and so
continuous with the dream and that it is an entirely new and separate context. In fact, in
some cases, part of the way the dream moves (of itself and so as part of its own
continuous movement) to a different conceptual order, rendering its initial materials
irrelevant or no longer meaningful, may be exactly by our waking up and so moving
beyond the whole thing. If so, that is, in these cases the dream itself builds to and brings
about our waking up, and so produces the shift to its own irrelevance in this way. It is
therefore in a sense continuous with its own discontinuity.
A rather neat possible version of this is when we actually forget the dream
immediately, and only later remember it and that we had forgotten it. We then experience
it exactly as something that had seemed important but then literally lost all meaning:
within our current experience, it ceased to have existed at all. Again, in some cases it may
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
38
be the dream’s own process, as a transition or relation between mutually exclusive sense
frameworks, which brings about this result.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
39
References
Barris, J. (2003). Paradox and the possibility of knowledge: The example of
Psychoanalysis. Selinsgrove, PA: Susquehanna University Press.
Barris, J. (2010). The logical structure of dreams and their relation to reality. Dreaming,
20, 1-18. Republished and revised in Barris, 2014.
Barris, J. (2012). The convergent conceptions of being in mainstream analytic and
postmodern continental philosophy. Metaphilosophy, 43, 592-618.
Barris, J. (2014). Sometimes always true: Undogmatic pluralism in politics, metaphysics,
and epistemology. New York: Fordham University Press.
Binswanger, L. (1963 [1930]). Dream and existence. Being-in-the-world: Selected papers
of Ludwig Binswanger (Jacob Needleman, Trans.). Riverdale, NY: Baen Books.
Boss, M. (1957 [1953]). The analysis of dreams (Arnold J. Pomerans, Trans.). London:
Rider.
Bremer, M. (2005). An introduction to paraconsistent logics. Frankfurt: Peter Lang.
Collingwood, R. G. (1940). An essay on metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Davidson, D. (1984). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. Inquiries into truth and
interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Derrida, J. (1981 [1972]). Positions (Alan Bass, Trans.). Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
Dewey J. (1938). Logic: The theory of inquiry. New York, NY: Henry Holt.
Dunlop, C. E. M. Ed. (1977). Philosophical essays on dreaming. Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Feyerabend, P. (1993). Against method. 3
rd
ed. London: Verso.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
40
Freud, S. (1976 [1900]). The interpretation of dreams (James Strachey, Trans.).
Harmondsworth: Penguin.
Freud, S. (1963 [1912]). Recommendations for physicians on the psychoanalytic method
of treatment (Joan Riviere, Trans.). Therapy and technique (Philip Rieff, Ed.).
New York, NY: Collier Books.
Gendlin, E. T. (1986). Let your body interpret your dreams. Wilmette, IL: Chiron
Publications.
Hall, E. W. (1960). Philosophical systems: A categorial analysis. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Jaspers, K. (1997 [1935]). Reason and existenz: Five lectures (William Earle, Trans.).
Milwaukee, WI: Marquette University Press.
Jung, C. G. (1974 [1934]). The practical use of dream-analysis. Dreams (R. F. C. Hull,
Trans.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kant, I. (1929 [1781/1787]). Critique of pure reason (Norman Kemp Smith, Trans.). New
York: St. Martin’s Press.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. 2
nd
ed. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Lyotard, J.-F. (1988 [1983]). The differend: Phrases in dispute. Trans. G. Van Den
Abbeele. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
MacIntyre, A. C. (1989). Relativism, power, and philosophy. Relativism: Interpretation
and confrontation (Michael Krausz, Ed.). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame Press.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
41
MacIntyre, A. C. (1988). Whose justice? Which rationality? Notre Dame, IN: University
of Notre Dame Press.
Malcolm, N. (1959). Dreaming. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Nagel, T. (1979). The absurd. Mortal questions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ortega y Gasset, J. (1960 [1929]). What is philosophy? (Mildred Adams, Trans.). New
York, NY: Norton.
Priest, G. (2001). An introduction to non-classical logic. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Priest, G., J. C. Beall, and Bradley Armour-Garb. Eds. (2004). The law of non-
contradiction: New philosophical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Putnam, H. Realism with a human face (James Conant, Ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1990.
Rechtschaffen, A. (1978). The single-mindedness and isolation of dreams. Sleep, 1, 97-
109.
Reik, T. (1948). Listening with the third ear: The inner experience of a psychoanalyst.
New York, NY: Farrar, Strauss, and Company.
Rorty, R. (1991). Objectivity, relativism, and truth: Philosophical papers volume 1. New
York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
States, B. O. (1993). Dreaming and storytelling. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
States, B. O. (1988). The rhetoric of dreams. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Taylor, C. (1985). Philosophical papers, vol. 2: Philosophy and the human sciences.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dreams As Meta-Conceptual Experience
42
Valberg, J. J. (2007). Dream, death, and the self. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press.
Winch, P. (1958). The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy. London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty (Denis Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). New
York, NY: Harper & Row.
Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.).
Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L. (1979). Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough. Trans. A. C. Miles.
Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1961 [1921]). Tractatus logico-philosophicus (D. F. Pears and B. F.
McGuinness, Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.